•  85
    Book reviews (review)
    with John Bacon, Alan R. White, Lawrence H. Davis, Gershon Weiler, Jeffrey Bub, Ilkka Niiniluoto, Yehuda Melzer, Zeev Levy, S. Biderman, Joseph Raz, Irwin C. Lieb, and Michael Ruse
    Philosophia 5 (3): 319-384. 1975.
  •  8
    The Practical World
    Idealistic Studies 29 (1-2): 1-31. 1999.
    'Everything,' Kant remarks, 'gravitates ultimately towards the practical.' Judging by 'everything,' Kant is fixing on some feature of reality that he regards as invariant across times, places, and people. Judging by 'ultimately,' Kant believes that the feature yields itself up only to penetrative philosophical scrutiny. The remark is, I believe, a key to 'the basic problem confronting any reader of [Kant],' his idealism.
  •  2
    Certainty, the cogito, and Cartesian Dualism
    Studia Leibnitiana 22 (2): 123-137. 1990.
    Il se peut du point de vue des etudiants qui s'approchent de la position contextuelle de Descartes, qu'il accepte la distinction reelle entre l'esprit et le corps parce qu'il n'a pas percu comment une forme d'explicarion mecanique-materialiste pourrait etre appropriee aux phenomenes psychologiques. Mais on pourrait demander la signification de cette proposition en ce qui concerne le raisonnement de Descartes pour Pactualite du dualisme. Je demontre que son raisonnement dans les Meditations est d…Read more
  •  1
    Examining Kant's critical philosophy, this study focusses upon its dialectical constitution and gauging its implications. It attempts to determine the meaning of the critical system more by determining the dialectical and rhetorical influences on Kant by focussing on its manifest reasoning. The volume begins by taking stock of meta-physical and meta-interpretive materials; then goes on to examine the major doctrines of the first Critique; and finally draws wider morals for Kant specifically and …Read more
  •  10
    Israelite Idol
    Philosophy and Theology 19 (1-2): 57-78. 2007.
    The Bible ridicules idolaters for bowing down to sticks and stones. Since idolaters worship what the sticks and stones stand for, not the sticks and stones themselves, isn’t the biblical position confused? At the basis of the Bible’s consistent refusal to observe the preceding distinction are found the conceptual underpinnings of its critique of idolatry. Men and women alone among creatures are inspired with God’s breath. Men and women alone among creatures, that is, are like God. They alone amo…Read more
  •  39
    The Dawn of Conceptuality
    Idealistic Studies 9 (3): 187-212. 1979.
    Ever ramifying debate over the correct analysis of linguistic representation unfolds against the backdrop of uncontested acceptance as baseline datum, by those aiming to determine the nature of the cognizing subject’s contact with the world, of language as the vehicle of factual packaging of experience. Given the easy two-way traffic in the contemporary lexicon between “concept” and “ word,” the modern reader’s antennae are not attuned to detect doctrinal parti pris when he encounters the mentio…Read more
  •  13
    Causation, Cognition, and Historical Typology
    Dialectica 34 (3): 211-227. 1980.
    SummaryBecause it is not generally appreciated that Hume's analysis of the causal tie as radically contingent or ‘irrational’ is bound up with his specialised theory of cognition, its historical position is widely misconceived. Even a rationalist like Spinoza would agree that if, as Hume maintains, the causal tie holds between items each of which is‘ adequately’ grasped independently of the other, i.e. between what Spinoza calls ‘substances’, then the tie is indeed irrational. Also, Kant does no…Read more
  •  19
    Interpreting bradley: the critique of fact-pluralism
    History and Philosophy of Logic 9 (2): 205-223. 1988.
    The typically dismissive treatment of Bradleian idealism, to the extent that it is based on philosophical criticism rather than historical bias, suffers from a failure to distinguish Bradley's negative views from his positive doctrines. But the intermingling of the two plays havoc in Bradley's own presentation, so that proper interpretation requires a particularly aggressive approach to the texts. Specifically, in denying a real multiplicity of facts, Bradley, though he may seem to be, is not at…Read more
  •  52
    God Is Love, Zeus Is Sex
    Philosophy and Theology 22 (1-2): 285-311. 2010.
    Does the character called “God” make an essential contribution to the [Hebrew] Bible? So far as religion and religiosity are concerned, the Bible minus the character called “God” is not theoretically incomplete. In other words, the Bible is not at core a theological document. From this it does not however follow that the deity of the Bible is theoretically otiose. The character called “God” plays a role that is indispensable for anthropological reasons. The self-definition and self-understanding…Read more
  •  32
    Spinoza à la mode: A defence of Spinozistic anti-pluralism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (1). 1997.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  20
    Cogito
    Modern Schoolman 70 (2): 81-98. 1993.
  •  4
    The Structure of Cartesian Scepticism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 21 (3): 343-357. 2010.
  •  39
    O God, O Montreal!
    Philo 17 (1): 23-43. 2014.
    In the book A Secular Age, Charles Taylor argues that: (1) modern secularism carries in it more than a trace residue of the explicitly religious way of thinking that it supersedes, and (2) the secular ensemble would not survive if the residue were filtered out. Modern secularism is not, in short, exclusively humanistic. Many who profess exclusive humanism, even perhaps the majority, are therefore—according to Taylor—exclusive humanists in name alone. My position is that Judeo-Christianity, in it…Read more
  •  38
  •  29
    Mind and body: Two real distinctions
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 22 (3): 347-359. 1984.
  •  11
    The Prussian Sphinx
    Idealistic Studies 25 (3): 255-280. 1995.
    Unhappy with a recent submission of mine, a referee for a journal specialising in the history of philosophy wagged a finger at what he or she called my ‘hermeneutical principles’. Though I am no stranger to the collegial woodshed, my initial reaction was nonetheless one of surprise. For had I then been asked about interpretive methodology I would have scoffed. The construer’s best course, I would have said, is to nose about the texts until some rough shape begins to emerge from the murk, and to …Read more
  •  43
    Cartesian Realism and G/P-Implosion
    Journal of Philosophical Research 23 307-329. 1998.
    Did Descartes make a revolutionary contribution to philosophy? Given the widespread application to him of the title ‘father of modem philosophy,’ the standard affirmative proves surprisingly difficult to justify. ln this paper I locate Descartes’s epoch-making philosophical shift. Descartes contributed a very strong idea of realism, an idea modelled in his cogito-argument. To grasp the contribution aright, it is however necessary to de-emphasise what is usually identified as his key contribution…Read more
  •  33
    John Locke
    Idealistic Studies 23 (2-3): 111-122. 1993.
    Throughout the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant locates his position relative to those of his predecessors and near contemporaries. Save for Spinoza, all the ‘greats’ of the early modern canon put in appearances. But while Kant’s idiom is respectful—Hume is referred to as ‘celebrated’ ; Berkeley is characterised as ‘good’ ; both Locke and Leibniz are called ‘illustrious’ —this ‘language of good will’ recalls Mark Antony’s ‘honourable man’. In fact, the debt Kant acknowledges to the prior toilers is…Read more
  •  17
    Although Western culture draws substantively on Athens and Jerusalem, hostility tends to be shown towards Jerusalem from the philosophical wing. I attempt to correct the imbalance. Philosophy, I argue, arose in the Greek context because of a problem of self‐confidence. ‘Philosophical rationality’ cannot therefore be taken as normative for rationality generally. The contrast between the Jerusalemite and the Athenian views of self and of the contrasting estimates and explanations of the efficacy o…Read more
  •  4
    How Philosophers See 'Red'
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 4 (1): 43-64. 1977.
    To what extent is conceptual analysis under strict semantic control? In an effort to show that conceptual structure transcends the linguistic dimension proper, the tensions within, and between, several current treatments of the concept red are revealed and explored. It is argued that certain extra-semantic factors — factors, broadly speaking, which concern the manner in which a concept applier interacts with the world as an extralinguistic agent - provide a backdrop against which conceptual anal…Read more
  •  25
    The Conceptual Structure of Reality
    Philosophical Quarterly 65 (261): 848-850. 2015.
  •  16
    Cognition and Predication: Towards a New Typology
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 33 (1). 1979.
  •  34
    Freedom and resentment and other essays
    Philosophia 6 (2): 321-332. 1976.
  •  27
    Book review (review)
    Philosophia 8 (2-3): 509-515. 1978.