•  92
    Berkeley's anti‐abstractionism
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (1). 1994.
  •  88
    A stratified bundle theory
    Synthese 42 (3). 1979.
  •  85
    Book reviews (review)
    with John Bacon, Alan R. White, Lawrence H. Davis, Gershon Weiler, Jeffrey Bub, Ilkka Niiniluoto, Yehuda Melzer, Zeev Levy, S. Biderman, Joseph Raz, Irwin C. Lieb, and Michael Ruse
    Philosophia 5 (3): 319-384. 1975.
  •  68
    In what respect, if any, is Kant a distinctively “critical” thinker? How does Kant’s “transcendentalism” differentiate his practice in metaphysics from that of the philosophers of the Cartesian tradition? How much does the success of Kant’s enterprise depend on the viability of the idea of the synthetic a priori? The issues that these questions raise came to a head for Kant in the attack on his novelty by the Leibnizean Johann August Eberhard, an attack to which Kant responded at length in the s…Read more
  •  64
    Book reviews (review)
    with Zeno Vendler, Gary Jason, George N. Schlesinger, Roberto Torretti, Bowman L. Clarke, Richard T. De George, Avner Cohen, Tecla Mazzarese, A. Modal Logician, and J. Gellman
    Philosophia 17 (2): 211-216. 1987.
  •  59
    The structure of cartesian scepticism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 21 (3): 343-357. 1983.
  •  59
    Invitation to a beheading: The career of philosophy
    Philosophia 28 (1-4): 39-66. 2001.
    Registrants for the academic study of philosophy, expecting an encounter with special cognitive products, regal truths, are soon enough disabused. Philosophy, its supposedly special access to the structure of things exploded, is relegated to sundry tasks of intellectual hygiene. I track down the source of the unrealistic view, anatomising what has a strong claim to be regarded as the regal enterprise’s inau¬gural reasoning—in Plato. When professionals consider the successor activity that is call…Read more
  •  56
    Transcendental Idealism and the End of Philosophy
    Metaphilosophy 24 (1-2): 97-112. 1993.
    The first "Critique", Kant states inaugurates a perfectly new science'. But this transcendental philosophy', for dealing in possibilities, not actualities, does not qualify as philosophy in the traditional sense. What Kant dubs transcendental idealism' "is" however an (ontological) doctrine about things. Kant's doctrinal stand is thus inconsistent with his description of transcendental enquiry. Since transcendental idealism gets its meaning from the contrast with Cartesian realism, it follows th…Read more
  •  52
    God Is Love, Zeus Is Sex
    Philosophy and Theology 22 (1-2): 285-311. 2010.
    Does the character called “God” make an essential contribution to the [Hebrew] Bible? So far as religion and religiosity are concerned, the Bible minus the character called “God” is not theoretically incomplete. In other words, the Bible is not at core a theological document. From this it does not however follow that the deity of the Bible is theoretically otiose. The character called “God” plays a role that is indispensable for anthropological reasons. The self-definition and self-understanding…Read more
  •  49
    Descartes, Scientia and Pure Enquiry
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (5): 873-886. 2011.
    In Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, Bernard Williams supplies an interpretation of Descartes's Meditations in which the meditator's clean sweep of initial beliefs is justified by a stance that abrogates all practical pressures: the stance of pure enquiry. Otherwise, Williams explains, it would not be reasonable to set many of the initial beliefs aside. Nowhere, however, does Descartes assert that his approach is in this sense ?pure?. It would of course be preferable if the meditator's rej…Read more
  •  44
  •  43
    Cartesian Realism and G/P-Implosion
    Journal of Philosophical Research 23 307-329. 1998.
    Did Descartes make a revolutionary contribution to philosophy? Given the widespread application to him of the title ‘father of modem philosophy,’ the standard affirmative proves surprisingly difficult to justify. ln this paper I locate Descartes’s epoch-making philosophical shift. Descartes contributed a very strong idea of realism, an idea modelled in his cogito-argument. To grasp the contribution aright, it is however necessary to de-emphasise what is usually identified as his key contribution…Read more
  •  43
    Doctrine and method in the philosophy of P. F. Strawson
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3): 364-383. 1976.
  •  41
    Abstraction and Determinacy
    Idealistic Studies 12 (1): 14-34. 1982.
    1. The distinction between the functions of sense and intellect in cognition is first given its modern form by Kant. According to one influential commentator, Jonathan Bennett, “Kant’s breakthrough” in fact consists precisely in liberating himself from his predecessors’ misconceptions in this regard. It is true that the categorial duality of receptivity and spontaneity—of intuition and concept—is not to be found in the major classical writings prior to Kant. In its place, one encounters a relati…Read more
  •  40
    Hume on Modes
    Hume Studies 3 (1): 32-50. 1977.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:32. HUME ON MODES As thorough a critic as Norman Kemp Smith states in his investigation of the Treatise that "Hume's treatment of... the complex ideas of modes... need not detain us." Whatever is interesting in this brief treatment, Smith suggests, rests on remarkable features of Humean doctrine, elsewhere expounded at length. This is true, I would agree, as a descriptive comment to the following degree. The category of modes is offi…Read more
  •  39
    O God, O Montreal!
    Philo 17 (1): 23-43. 2014.
    In the book A Secular Age, Charles Taylor argues that: (1) modern secularism carries in it more than a trace residue of the explicitly religious way of thinking that it supersedes, and (2) the secular ensemble would not survive if the residue were filtered out. Modern secularism is not, in short, exclusively humanistic. Many who profess exclusive humanism, even perhaps the majority, are therefore—according to Taylor—exclusive humanists in name alone. My position is that Judeo-Christianity, in it…Read more
  •  39
    The First Professor of Biblical Philosophy
    Sophia 52 (3): 503-519. 2013.
    The notion of a particular is what makes the Bible (the reference is to the Hebrew Scriptures) an original position in philosophy. (Particulars are self-contained spatio-temporal entities, and hence, though present in the system that is nature, are not essentially parts of it.) The early chapters of Genesis develop a comprehensive (anti-pagan) conceptualization of reality that gives particularity its due. Whether particularity can be secured without a fully extra-natural anchorage (i.e., without…Read more
  •  39
    On One Leg: The Stability of Monotheism
    Philosophy and Theology 26 (1): 187-206. 2014.
    A potential proselyte asks the great rabbi Hillel to explain the Torah to him while he stands ‘on one leg.’ Hillel responds with, essentially, the Golden Rule. This Talmudic anecdote is invariably read as critical of anyone who wants a Torah for Dummies. I offer a different interpretation. The Torah-based position, theologically speaking, rests on one principle and one principle alone, God. ‘How can an account of the creation as a whole rest on one principle only? Won’t such a structure stand un…Read more
  •  39
    Transcendental Idealism
    Idealistic Studies 18 (3): 247-265. 1988.
    “By transcendental idealism,” Kant explains, “I mean the doctrine that appearances are … representations only, not things in themselves, and that time and space are therefore only sensible forms of our intuition, not determinations given as existing by themselves, nor conditions of objects viewed as things in themselves” ; “… by our sensibility … we do not apprehend [things in themselves] in any fashion whatsoever”. The phenomenality of the objective realm, according to Kant, follows from the fa…Read more
  •  38
    The Dawn of Conceptuality
    Idealistic Studies 9 (3): 187-212. 1979.
    Ever ramifying debate over the correct analysis of linguistic representation unfolds against the backdrop of uncontested acceptance as baseline datum, by those aiming to determine the nature of the cognizing subject’s contact with the world, of language as the vehicle of factual packaging of experience. Given the easy two-way traffic in the contemporary lexicon between “concept” and “ word,” the modern reader’s antennae are not attuned to detect doctrinal parti pris when he encounters the mentio…Read more
  •  38
  •  37
    Tractatus: Pluralism or monism?
    Mind 89 (353): 17-36. 1980.
  •  37
    The Prussian Sphinx
    Idealistic Studies 25 (3): 255-280. 1995.
    Unhappy with a recent submission of mine, a referee for a journal specialising in the history of philosophy wagged a finger at what he or she called my ‘hermeneutical principles’. Though I am no stranger to the collegial woodshed, my initial reaction was nonetheless one of surprise. For had I then been asked about interpretive methodology I would have scoffed. The construer’s best course, I would have said, is to nose about the texts until some rough shape begins to emerge from the murk, and to …Read more
  •  36
    Book reviews (review)
    with Kenneth S. Friedman, Donald Gotterbarn, Bryan G. Norton, David S. Schwarz, and Walter P. Van Stigt
    Philosophia 9 (1): 805-813. 1979.
  •  35
    Of mice and men: God and the canadian supreme court
    Ratio Juris 21 (1): 107-124. 2008.
    In a recent 5‐to‐4 decision, the Supreme Court of Canada denied to Harvard University a patent on a genetically modified mouse. In their reasoning, the majority Justices, concerned obviously about the implications of granting the patent for the human case, argue that higher organisms (mammals) are not “compositions of matter” in the sense intended by the Canadian Patent Act. But if a mouse is not a composition of matter, what—indeed, what on earth—is it? As the minority Justices complain, the ma…Read more
  •  34
    Freedom and resentment and other essays
    Philosophia 6 (2): 321-332. 1976.
  •  33
    John Locke
    Idealistic Studies 23 (2-3): 111-122. 1993.
    Throughout the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant locates his position relative to those of his predecessors and near contemporaries. Save for Spinoza, all the ‘greats’ of the early modern canon put in appearances. But while Kant’s idiom is respectful—Hume is referred to as ‘celebrated’ ; Berkeley is characterised as ‘good’ ; both Locke and Leibniz are called ‘illustrious’ —this ‘language of good will’ recalls Mark Antony’s ‘honourable man’. In fact, the debt Kant acknowledges to the prior toilers is…Read more
  •  33
    RÉSUMÉ: La Bible éclaire la distinction kantienne entre les apparences et les choses en soi. Les deux récits bibliques de la création, dans Genèse 1 et 2, offrent différentes analyses ontologiques, et seule la deuxième est, comme les apparences de Kant, relative à la condition humaine. Mais, tandis que l’autre région dont Kant parle est sans caractérisation positive, la Bible décrit amplement le monde tel qu’il est avant l’avènement des hommes et des femmes. La Bible traite de ce domaine du poin…Read more