•  43
    How Mandatory Can We Make Vaccination?
    Public Health Ethics 15 (3): 220-232. 2022.
    The novel coronavirus (SARS-CoV-2) pandemic has refocused attention on the issue of mandatory vaccination. Some have suggested that vaccines ought to be mandatory, while others propose more moderate alternatives, such as incentives. This piece surveys a range of possible interventions, ranging from mandates through to education. All may have their place, depending on circumstances. However, it is worth clarifying the options available to policymakers, since there is sometimes confusion over whet…Read more
  •  38
    Recent Critics of Mill's Qualitative Hedonism
    Philosophy 91 (4): 503-521. 2016.
    Two recent critics of Mill's qualitative hedonism, Michael Hauskeller and Kristin Schaupp, argue that Mill's distinction between higher and lower pleasures was largely unsuccessful. They allege that Mill failed to demonstrate that some pleasures are lexically preferred to others, and indeed that this can be shown false by the fact that most people would not renounce supposedly lower pleasures, such as chocolate or sex, even for greater amounts of higher pleasures, such as reading or opera. I res…Read more
  •  36
    A Millian Case for Censoring Vaccine Misinformation
    Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 20 (1): 115-124. 2023.
    The spread of vaccine misinformation may contribute to vaccine refusal/hesitancy and consequent harms. Nonetheless, censorship is often rejected on the grounds of free expression. This article examines John Stuart Mill’s influential defence of free expression but finds that his arguments for freedom apply only to normal, reasonably favourable circumstances. In other cases, it may be permissible to restrict freedom, including freedom of speech. Thus, while Mill would ordinarily defend the right t…Read more
  •  30
    Accountability for Reasonableness or Equality of Resources?
    American Journal of Bioethics 18 (3): 49-50. 2018.
  •  30
    Democracy and Future Generations
    Philosophy and Public Issues - Filosofia E Questioni Pubbliche. 2014.
    Download
  •  27
    Democracy-as-fairness: justice, equal chances and lotteries
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 2 (1): 154. 2009.
  •  27
    Equality in the allocation of scarce vaccines
    Les Ateliers de l'Éthique / the Ethics Forum 13 (3): 65-84. 2018.
    In the event of a pandemic, demand for vaccines may exceed supply. One proposal for allocating vaccines is to use a lottery, to give all citizens an equal chance, either of getting the vaccine or of surviving. However, insistence on strict equality can result in seriously suboptimal outcomes. I argue that the requirement to treat all citizens impartially need not be interpreted to require equal chances, particularly where citizens are differently situated. Assuming that we want to save lives, we…Read more
  •  27
    J.S. Mill and market harms: a response to Endörfer
    Economics and Philosophy 1-6. forthcoming.
    Endörfer has recently argued that proponents of the harm principle are wrong to exempt market harms as potential justifications for state interference. I argue that – contrary to suggestions in Endörfer’s article – John Stuart Mill did not exempt market harms from his harm principle. On Mill’s view, the state can (as a matter of principle) legitimately interfere with free markets to prevent market harms where they occur but, on the whole, it is better policy not to interfere. Mill’s general pref…Read more
  •  25
    Fetuses are not adult humans: a response to Miller on abortion
    Journal of Medical Ethics. forthcoming.
    Miller has recently argued that fetuses have the same inherent value as non-disabled adults. However, we do not need to postulate some property possessed equally by all humans, including fetuses, in order to explain the equality of non-disabled adults. It would suffice if there were some property possessed by all non-disabled adults, but not by fetuses.
  •  25
    Upsetting the balance on sex selection
    Bioethics 33 (9): 1022-1028. 2019.
    It is widely assumed that the strongest case for permitting non‐medical sex selection is where parents aim at family balance. This piece criticizes one representative attempt to justify sex selection for family balance. Kluge (2007) assumes that some couples may seek sex selection because they hold discriminatory values, but this need not impugn those who merely have preferences, without evaluative commitments, for a particular sex. This is disputed by those who see any sex selection as inherent…Read more
  •  24
    Douglas Diekema influentially argues that interference with parental decisions is not in fact guided by the child’s best interests, but rather by a more permissive standard, which he calls the harm principle. This article first seeks to clarify this alternative position and defend it against certain existing criticisms, before offering a new criticism and alternative. This ‘harm principle’ has been criticized for (i) lack of adequate moral grounding, and (ii) being as indeterminate as the best i…Read more
  •  21
    Understanding (and) consent: a response to MacKay
    Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (3): 203-204. 2016.
  •  20
    Donald Trump promised to build a wall along the US–Mexico border and to make Mexico pay for it, but this seems to violate the principle of ‘no taxation without representation’ on which the United States was founded. Some democratic theorists propose even more radical principles of inclusion, such as that all those affected by or subject to a decision should have a say in it. But even a more moderate principle, requiring that those who pay must be represented, is sufficient to show that Trump's p…Read more
  •  18
    Immigration, Rights and Democracy
    Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory 58 58-77. 2011.
    Arash Abizadeh has recently argued that political communities have no right to close their borders unilaterally, since by doing so they subject outsiders to coercion which lacks democratic justification. His conclusion is that any legitimate regime of border controls must be justified to outsiders. David Miller has sought to defend closed borders by distinguishing between coercion and prevention and arguing that the latter does not require democratic justification. This paper explores a differen…Read more
  •  17
    Sex Discrimination, Gender Balance, Justice and Publicity in Admissions
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 27 (1): 59-71. 2010.
    abstract This paper examines the problem of selecting a number of candidates to receive a good (admission) from a pool in which there are more qualified applicants than places. I observe that it is rarely possible to order all candidates according to some relevant criterion, such as academic merit, since these standards are inevitably somewhat vague. This means that we are often faced with the task of making selections between near‐enough equal candidates. I survey one particular line of respons…Read more
  •  16
    In a recent article, Fiona Woollard draws attention to a number of problems, both theoretical and pragmatic, with current discourse around infant feeding. References both to the ‘benefits of breastfeeding’ and ‘harms of formula’ are problematic, since there is no obvious baseline of comparison against which to make these evaluations. Further, she highlights the pragmatic consequences of these linguistic choices. Saying that formula feeding harms babies, for instance, is likely to exacerbate feel…Read more
  •  11
    Wolff's Argument for the Rejection of State Authority
    In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments, Wiley‐blackwell. 2011-09-16.
  •  10
    Tooley on Abortion and Infanticide
    In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments, Wiley‐blackwell. 2011-09-16.
  •  10
    Paternalism, with and without identity
    Journal of Medical Ethics 49 (6): 409-410. 2023.
    Interference is paternalistic when it restricts an individual’s freedom for their own good. Anti-paternalists, such as John Stuart Mill, object to this for various reasons, including that the individual is usually a better judge of her own interests than the would-be paternalist. However, Wilkinson argues that a Parfitian reductivist approach to personal identity opens the door to what he calls ‘identity-relative paternalism’ where someone’s present action is restricted for the sake of a differe…Read more
  •  9
    Parfit's Leveling down Argument against Egalitarianism
    In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments, Wiley‐blackwell. 2011-09-16.
  •  7
    Taurek on Numbers don't Count
    In Michael Bruce & Steven Barbone (eds.), Just the Arguments, Wiley‐blackwell. 2011-09-16.
  •  6
    Mill's Conception of Happiness
    In Christopher Macleod & Dale E. Miller (eds.), A Companion to Mill, John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. 2016.
    Mill appears to subscribe to the hedonist view that happiness consists in pleasure and the absence of pain, yet he departs from the Benthamite tradition by suggesting that some pleasures are more valuable than others. I suggest that the value of a pleasure depends on its contribution to happiness. Other things equal, more pleasure is more conducive to happiness than less, but some pleasures are also more valuable than others, quantity being equal. These more valuable pleasures are those that Mil…Read more
  •  6
    Opt‐out, mandated choice and informed consent
    Bioethics 37 (9): 862-868. 2023.
    A number of authors criticise opt-out (or ‘deemed consent’) systems for failing to secure valid consent to organ donation. Further, several suggest that mandated choice offers a more ethical alternative. This article responds to criticisms that opt-out does not secure informed consent. If we assume current (low) levels of public awareness, then the explicit consent secured under mandated choice will not be informed either. Conversely, a mandated choice policy might be justifiable if accompanied …Read more
  •  5
    Harm to What Others? J. S. Mill's Ambivalence Regarding Third-Party Harm
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 62 (2): 263-287. 2024.
    Abstractabstract:John Stuart Mill's harm principle holds that an individual's freedom can only be restricted to prevent harm to others. However, there is an important ambiguity between a strong version, which limits legitimate interference to self-defense and therefore prohibits society from protecting third parties (those who are not its members), and a narrow version, which grants any society universal jurisdiction to prevent nonconsensual harms, no matter who is harmed. Mill sometimes appeals…Read more
  •  4
    Healthcare strikes and the ethics of voting in ballots
    Journal of Medical Ethics. forthcoming.
    There has been much discussion of the justifiability of strikes by healthcare workers, but comparatively little discussion of the political processes through which strikes occur. This article focuses on the Trade Union Act 2016, which currently governs strike ballots in the UK. This legislation has important implications for healthcare workers being balloted on strikes (or other forms of industrial action). The article first explains the legal requirements for a strike mandate and illustrates ho…Read more