• Nietzsche and the Morality Critics
    In John Richardson & Brian Leiter (eds.), Nietzsche, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  •  28
    Moral Psychology with Nietzsche
    Oxford University Press. 2019.
    Brian Leiter draws on empirical psychology to defend a set of radical ideas from Nietzsche: there is no objectively true morality, there is no free will, no one is ever morally responsible, and our conscious thoughts play almost no significant role in our actions. Nietzsche emerges as not just a great philosopher but a prescient psychologist.
  •  62
    Rorty’s Rejection of Philosophy
    Analyse & Kritik 41 (1): 23-30. 2019.
    I argue that the real puzzle about Richard Rorty’s intellectual development is not why he gave up on ‘analytic’ philosophy-he had never been much committed to that research agenda, even before it became moribund-but why, beginning with Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (PMN), he gave up on the central concerns of philosophy going back to antiquity. In addition to Rorty’s published works, I draw on biographical information about Rorty’s undergraduate and graduate education to support this asses…Read more
  •  134
    The Truth Is Terrible
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 49 (2): 151-173. 2018.
    The “terrible” existential truths about the human situation raise Schopenhauer's question: why continue living at all? Nietzsche's answer is that only viewed in terms of aesthetic values can life itself be “justified”. But how could the fact that life exemplifies aesthetic value restore our attachment to life in the face of these terrible existential truths? I suggest that there are two keys to understanding Nietzsche's answer: first, his assimilation of aesthetic pleasure to a kind of sublimate…Read more
  •  97
    The innocence of becoming: Nietzsche against guilt
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (1): 70-92. 2019.
    ABSTRACTI offer an interpretation of Nietzsche's striking idea of ‘the innocence of becoming’, and a partial defense of its import, namely, that no one is ever morally responsible or guilty for what they do and that many of the so-called reactive attitudes are misplaced. I focus primarily, though not exclusively, on the arguments as set out in Twilight of the Idols. First, there is Nietzsche's hypothesis, partly psychological and partly historical or anthropological, that the ideas of ‘free’ act…Read more
  •  23
    A teoria nietzschiana da vontade
    Cadernos Nietzsche 38 (3): 17-49. 2017.
  • Oxford Studies in Legal Philosophy, vol. 2 (edited book)
    with L. Green
    Oxford UP. 2013.
  •  23
    Nietzsche's Naturalism and Nineteenth-Century Biology
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 48 (1): 71-82. 2017.
    Christian Emden has written an informative if sometimes philosophically frustrating book about Nietzsche’s engagement with both neo-Kantian philosophers 1 and the life sciences from the 1840s onward. Emden documents the preceding with an eye to shedding light not only on Nietzsche’s naturalism, on “what does it mean to ‘translate humanity back into nature’” as Nietzsche put it in BGE, but also on what Emden calls “the problem of normativity,” variously stated as how to “obtain an understanding o…Read more
  •  3
    Nietzsche on Morality
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 729-740. 2005.
  •  22
    Nietzsche's Metaethics: Against the Privilege Readings
    European Journal of Philosophy 8 (3): 277-297. 2000.
  • In Chapters I-III, I argue that Nietzsche is a critic of "morality" in the sense of any system of values that has one or both of the following features: it presupposes the truth of certain descriptive claims about human agency, in the sense that for the evaluative categories to be intelligibly applied to persons these claims must be true ; it favors the interests of the "lowest" at the expense of the "highest" men, the embodiments of human excellence. I illustrate, in particular, how this latter…Read more
  •  2
    Is there an american furisprudence?
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17 (2): 367-387. 1997.
    BRIAN LEITER; Is There An ‘American’ Jurisprudence?, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Volume 17, Issue 2, 1 July 1997, Pages 367–387, https://doi.org/10.1093/oj.
  •  77
    Why Marxism Still Does Not Need Normative Theory
    Analyse & Kritik 37 (1-2): 23-50. 2015.
    Marx did not have a normative theory, that is, a theory that purported to justify, discursively and systematically, his normative opinions, to show them to be rationally obligatory or objectively valid. In this regard, Marx was obviously not alone: almost everyone, including those who lead what are widely regarded as exemplary ‘moral’ lives, decide and act on the basis of normative intuitions and inclinations that fall far short of a theory. Yet self-proclaimed Marxists like G. A. Cohen and Jurg…Read more
  • Introduction
    In The Future for Philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 1--23. 2004.
  •  248
    Nietzsche's theory of the will
    Philosophers' Imprint 7 1-15. 2007.
    The essay offers a philosophical reconstruction of Nietzsche’s theory of the will, focusing on (1) Nietzsche’s account of the phenomenology of “willing” an action, the experience we have which leads us (causally) to conceive of ourselves as exercising our will; (2) Nietzsche’s arguments that the experiences picked out by the phenomenology are not causally connected to the resulting action (at least not in a way sufficient to underwrite ascriptions of moral responsibility); and (3) Nietzsche’s ac…Read more
  •  42
    Introduction: From legal realism to naturalized jurisprudence -- A note on legal indeterminacy -- Part I. American legal realism and its critics -- Rethinking legal realism: toward a naturalized jurisprudence (1997) -- Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered (2001) -- Is there an "American" jurisprudence? (1997) -- Postscript to Part I: Interpreting legal realism -- Part II. Ways of naturalizing jurisprudence -- Legal realism, hard positivism, and the limits of conceptual analysis (199…Read more
  •  2
    The Philosophical Gourmet
    The Philosophers' Magazine 8 8-8. 1999.
  •  43
    Legal positivism
    In Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, Blackwell. 1996.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Jurisprudence: Method and Subject Matter Legality and Authority Positivism: Austin vs. Hart The Authority of Law Judicial Discretion Incorporationism and Legality Raz' s Theory of Authority Incorporationism and Authority Conclusion Postscript References.
  •  108
    Nietzsche and aestheticism
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (2): 275-290. 1992.
  • I confess to uncertainty about whether Professor Hoekema's reply http://ndpr.icaap.org/content/archives/2002/10/hoekema=leiter.html) to my comments on his review of Wilshire http://ndpr.icaap.org/content/archives/2002/10/leiter=hoekema.html) is just careless or intentionally dishonest. It is plainly quite misleading.
  •  64
    Moralities are a sign-language of the affects
    Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1-2): 237-258. 2013.
    This essay offers an interpretation and partial defense of Nietzsche's idea that moralities and moral judgments are “sign-languages” or “symptoms” of our affects, that is, of our emotions or feelings. According to Nietzsche, as I reconstruct his view, moral judgments result from the interaction of two kinds of affective responses: first, a “basic affect” of inclination toward or aversion from certain acts, and then a further affective response to that basic affect. I argue that Nietzsche views b…Read more
  •  36
  • Law and objectivity
    In Jules Coleman & Scott J. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence & Philosophy of Law, Oxford University Press. pp. 969--89. 2002.
  •  16
    Opinion
    The Philosophers' Magazine 10 8-8. 2000.