•  92
    Marion, Jean-Luc. Cartesian Questions: Method and Metaphysics (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 54 (1): 160-161. 2000.
  •  103
    Ariew, Roger. Descartes and the Last Scholastics (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 54 (1): 128-129. 2000.
  • Leibniz's Correspondence with Des Bosses
    In Paul Lodge (ed.), Leibniz and His Correspondents, Uk ;cambridge University Press. 2004.
  •  167
    Leibniz
    The Leibniz Review 16 119-121. 2006.
  •  212
    Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) was one of the great thinkers of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries and is known as the last “universal genius”. He made deep and important contributions to the fields of metaphysics, epistemology, logic, philosophy of religion, as well as mathematics, physics, geology, jurisprudence, and history. Even the eighteenth century French atheist and materialist Denis Diderot, whose views could not have stood in greater opposition to those of Leibniz, could n…Read more
  •  198
    Perfection, power and the passions in Spinoza and Leibniz
    Revue Roumaine de la Philosophie 51 (1-2): 21-38. 2007.
    In a short piece written most likely in the 1690s and given the title by Loemker of “On Wisdom,” Leibniz says the following: “...we see that happiness, pleasure, love, perfection, being, power, freedom, harmony, order, and beauty are all tied to each other, a truth which is rightly perceived by few.”1 Why is this? That is, why or how are these concepts tied to each other? And, why have so few understood this relation? Historians of philosophy are familiar with the fact that both Spinoza and Leib…Read more
  •  128
    Between Two Worlds: A Reading of Descartes’s Meditations
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 48 (1). 2009.
    In his Between Two Worlds: A Reading of Descartes’s Meditations, John Carriero presents a sustained and sensitive interpretation of this seminal work of modern philosophy. The two worlds of the title are the worlds of Scholastic philosophy on the one side, and of the mechanical philosophy on the other, and it is Carriero’s argument that the Meditations are most helpfully understood against the background of Thomistic Scholasticism. In particular, Carriero shows that there is a deep difference be…Read more
  •  1
    In this paper, the author examines Leibniz inconsistent treatments of the existence predicate in his formulations of the ontological argument and elsewhere. It is shown that, contrary to expectations, Leibniz at times adumbrates insights often attributed to Kant and Frege.
  •  193
    One of the more interesting topics debated by Leibniz and Locke and one that has received comparatively little critical commentary is the nature of essences and the classification of the natural world.1 This topic, moreover, is of tremendous importance, occupying a position at the intersection of the metaphysics of individual beings, modality, epistemology, and philosophy of language. And, while it goes back to Plato, who wondered if we could cut nature at its joints, as Nicholas Jolley has poin…Read more
  •  100
    Keller, Pierre. Kant and the Demands of Self-Consciousness (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 54 (2): 446-447. 2000.
  •  388
    Kant’s Thinker
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 49 (4): 502-503. 2011.
    Kant’s Thinker is an excellent and important addition to the literature. In it, Patricia Kitcher aims at arriving at a comprehensive understanding of Kant’s theory of the cognitive subject. To this end, she analyzes a central component of the most notoriously difficult part of the Critique of Pure Reason, the theory of the unity of apperception in the chapter on the Transcendental Deduction of the Categories. In Kitcher’s view, the ultimate payoff of such a study is that Kant’s theory can “provi…Read more
  •  76
    The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1): 142-144. 1997.
  •  86
    Descartes' Konzeption des Systems der Philosophie (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (3): 440-442. 2001.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.3 (2001) 440-442 [Access article in PDF] Reinhard Lauth. Descartes ' Konzeption des Systems der Philosophie. Stuttgart (Bad Cannstatt): Frommann-Holzboog, 1998. Pp. x + 227 pp. Cloth, DM 64.00. Reinhard Lauth's Descartes ' Konzeption des Systems der Philosophie is an interesting addition to the literature on Descartes. Written by a renowned scholar of German Idealism, it does not represent an a…Read more
  •  172
    Notiones sunt Entium, aut Respectuum. Entia sunt Res aut Modi. Res sunt substantiae aut phaenomenae. Substantiae sunt vel simplices vel compositae. Substantia simplex est Monas; Monas autem est vel primitiva Deus, a quo omnia; vel derivativa. Et ha[e]c vel perceptiva tantum, vel etiam sensitiva; et haec vel sensitiva tantum vel etiam intellectiva quae et spiritus appellatur. Rursus Monas vel est Anima corporis vel est separata; haec vel creata (ut plerique volunt etsi ego an creata sint monades …Read more
  •  86
    Leibniz: Metaphilosophy and metaphysics, 1666-1686 (review)
    The Leibniz Review 15 119-121. 2006.
  •  64
    Leibniz and Adam
    The Leibniz Review 5 29-32. 1995.
    The book under review contains a selection of the papers presented at the conference “Leibniz and Adam,” held in Tel Aviv and Jerusalem from December 29, 1991 to January 2, 1992. The object of the conference and the book was to consider the role of Adam, the first man, in Leibniz’s thought and, in doing so, “to provide an unusual view of the interrelations between his metaphysics, philosophy of religion, philosophy of language, theory of knowledge, logic, attidude vis-à-vis mysticism, philosophy…Read more
  •  94
    The platonic Leibniz
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (1). 2003.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  139
    Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity, 1650-1750 (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (3): 399-400. 2002.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 40.3 (2002) 399-400 [Access article in PDF] Book Review Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity, 1650-1750 Jonathan I. Israel. Radical Enlightenment: Philosophy and the Making of Modernity, 1650-1750. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. Pp. xx + 810. Cloth, $45.00. Jonathan Israel's goal in this excellent book is to show that we cannot fully understand the high Enlightenme…Read more
  •  281
    The connection between Spinoza and Nietzsche has often been remarked upon in the literature on the two thinkers.1 Not surprisingly, Nietzsche himself first noticed the similarity between his (earlier) thought and the thought of Spinoza, remarking to Overbeck in an oft-quoted postcard, “I have a precursor, and what a precursor!” He goes on to say, “Not only is his over-all tendency like mine – making knowledge the most powerful affect – but in five main points of his doctrine I recognize myself; …Read more
  •  101
    Review: Westphal, Kant's Transcendental Proof of Realism
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (4): 665-666. 2006.
    Brandon Look - Kant's Transcendental Proof of Realism - Journal of the History of Philosophy 44:4 Journal of the History of Philosophy 44.4 665-666 Muse Search Journals This Journal Contents Reviewed by Brandon C. Look University of Kentucky Kenneth R. Westphal. Kant's Transcendental Proof of Realism. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp. x + 299. Cloth, $80.00. Westphal's book is a rich and exciting contribution to the field of Kant studies. Its claims run counter to much contemporary…Read more
  •  255
    Leibniz and the Shelf of Essence
    The Leibniz Review 15 27-47. 2005.
    This paper addresses D. C. Williams’s question, “How can Leibniz know that he is a member of the actual world and not merely a possible monad on the shelf of essence?” A variety of answers are considered. Ultimately, it is argued that no particular perception of a state of affairs in the world can warrant knowledge of one’s actuality, nor can the awareness of any property within oneself; rather, it is the nature of experience itself, with the flow of perceptions, that guarantees our actuality. A…Read more
  •  81
    Kant's Transcendental Proof of Realism (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 44 (4): 665-666. 2006.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Kant’s Transcendental Proof of RealismBrandon C. LookKenneth R. Westphal. Kant’s Transcendental Proof of Realism. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004. Pp. x + 299. Cloth, $80.00.Westphal's book is a rich and exciting contribution to the field of Kant studies. Its claims run counter to much contemporary discussion of Kant's theoretical philosophy and indeed challenge some of Kant's fundamental doctrines, but the arg…Read more
  •  100
    The Four-Category Ontology (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 60 (3): 666-668. 2007.
  •  790
    Existence, Essence, et Expression: Leibniz sur 'toutes les absurdités du Dieu de Spinoza'
    In Pierre-Francois Moreau, Mogens Laerke & Raphaële Andrault (eds.), Spinoza et Leibniz: Rencontres, controverse, réceptions, Presses De L'université Paris-sorbonne. pp. 57-82. 2014.
    That Leibniz finds the philosophy of Spinoza horrifyingly wrong is obvious to anyone who reads Leibniz’s work; that Leibniz finds Spinozism so seductive that his own system is in danger of collapsing into it is less obvious but, I believe, equally true. The difference here is not so much between an exoteric and an esoteric philosophy suggested by Russell2 but between a thorough-going rationalism on the part of Spinoza and Leibniz’s “mitigated rationalism” – mitigated by the exigencies of his ort…Read more