•  243
    Recently, Terry Horgan and Matjaž Potrč have defended the thesis of ‘existence monism’, according to which the whole cosmos is the only concrete object. Their arguments appeal largely to considerations concerning vagueness. Crucially, they claim that ontological vagueness is impossible, and one key assumption in their defence of this claim is that vagueness always involves ‘sorites-susceptibility’. I aim to challenge both the claim and this assumption. As a consequence, I seek to undermine their…Read more
  •  136
    Form without matter
    Ratio 11 (3). 1998.
    Three different concepts of matter are identified: matter as what a thing is immediately made of, matter as stuff of a certain kind, and matter in the (dubious) sense of material ‘substratum’. The doctrine of hylomorphism, which regards every individual concrete thing as being ‘combination’ of matter and form, is challenged. Instead it is urged that we do well to identify an individual concrete thing with its own particular ‘substantial form’. The notions of form and matter, far from being corre…Read more
  • Review of Metaphysical Essays (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. forthcoming.
  •  54
    Locke, Martin and substance (contributions to metaphysics)
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (201): 498--514. 2000.
  •  195
    Abstraction, Properties, and Immanent Realism
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 2 195-205. 1999.
    Objects which philosophers have traditionally categorized as abstract are standardly referred to by complex noun phrases of certain canonical forms, such as ‘the set of Fs’, ‘the number of Fs’, ‘the proposition that P’, and ‘the property of being F’. It is no accident that such noun phrases are well-suited to appear in ‘Fregean’ identity-criteria, or ‘abstraction’ principles, for which Frege’s criterion of identity for cardinal numbers provides the paradigm. Notoriously, such principlesare apt t…Read more
  •  110
    Serious endurantism and the strong unity of human persons
    In Benedikt Schick, Edmund Runggaldier & Ludger Honnefelder (eds.), Unity and Time in Metaphysics, Walter De Gruyter. pp. 67. 2009.
  •  91
    On Being a Cat
    Analysis 42 (3). 1982.
  •  138
    Entity, identity and unity
    Erkenntnis 48 (2-3): 191-208. 1998.
    I propose a fourfold categorisation of entities according to whether or not they possess determinate identity-conditions and whether or not they are determinately countable. Some entities – which I call ‘individual objects’ – have both determinate identity and determinate countability: for example, persons and animals. In the case of entities of a kind K belonging to this category, we are in principle always entitled to expect there to be determinate answers to such questions as ‘Is x the same K…Read more
  •  126
    Two Notions of Being: Entity and Essence
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 62 23-48. 2008.
  •  76
    Review of John Hawthorne, Metaphysical Essays (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2007 (1). 2007.
  •  1
    Kinds of Being
    Philosophy 66 (256): 248-249. 1989.
  • Noonan, "Harold, Personal Identity" (review)
    Mind 99 (n/a): 477. 1990.
  •  3
    Dualism
    In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  98
    The mind in nature
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 17 (4). 2009.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  274
    Real essentialism – David S. Oderberg
    Philosophical Quarterly 60 (240): 648-652. 2010.
  •  512
    What is the Source of Our Knowledge of Modal Truths?
    Mind 121 (484): 919-950. 2012.
    There is currently intense interest in the question of the source of our presumed knowledge of truths concerning what is, or is not, metaphysically possible or necessary. Some philosophers locate this source in our capacities to conceive or imagine various actual or non-actual states of affairs, but this approach is open to certain familiar and seemingly powerful objections. A different and ostensibly more promising approach has been developed by Timothy Williamson, according to which our capaci…Read more
  •  103
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  159
    E. J. Lowe; Coinciding objects: in defence of the ‘standard account’, Analysis, Volume 55, Issue 3, 1 July 1995, Pages 171–178, https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/5.
  •  22
    The Determinists Have Run Out of Luck—For a Good Reason
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 745-748. 2008.
  •  33
    Substance and Selfhood
    Philosophy 66 (255). 1991.
    How could the self be a substance? There are various ways in which it could be, some familiar from the history of philosophy. I shall be rejecting these more familiar substantivalist approaches, but also the non-substantival theories traditionally opposed to them. I believe that the self is indeed a substance—in fact, that it is a simple or noncomposite substance—and, perhaps more remarkably still, that selves are, in a sense, self-creating substances. Of course, if one thinks of the notion of s…Read more
  •  263
    Reply to le poidevin and Mellor
    Mind 96 (384): 539-542. 1987.
    In ‘Time, Change and the “Indexical Fallacy”’,1 Robin Le Poidevin and D. H. Mellor criticize an earlier paper of mine2 both for failing to rebut an argument of McTaggart's and for failing to explain why time is the dimension of change. I consider that their criticisms miss the mark on both scores, partly through misrepresentation of my views and partly through defective argumentation
  •  183
    Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum have recently attacked causal necessitarianism – the doctrine that causes necessitate their effects – on the grounds that causation does not survive what they describe as the test of antecedent strengthening. This article shows that there are credible conditional logics which do not sanction this test, thereby providing an escape route for proponents of causal necessitarianism from Mumford and Anjum's argument