•  70
    Substance and Selfhood
    Philosophy 66 (255): 81-99. 1991.
    How could the self be a substance? There are various ways in which it could be, some familiar from the history of philosophy. I shall be rejecting these more familiar substantivalist approaches, but also the non-substantival theories traditionally opposed to them. I believe that the self is indeed a substance—in fact, that it is a simple or noncomposite substance—and, perhaps more remarkably still, that selves are, in a sense, self-creating substances. Of course, if one thinks of the notion of s…Read more
  •  100
    E. J. Lowe; Indicative and counterfactual conditionals, Analysis, Volume 39, Issue 3, 1 June 1979, Pages 139–141, https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/39.3.139.
  •  442
    The metaphysics of abstract objects
    Journal of Philosophy 92 (10): 509-524. 1995.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 97 (387): 484-487. 1988.
  •  30
    What do we see directly?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (3): 277-286. 1986.
  •  88
    Reply to Noonan
    Analysis 47 (4). 1987.
  •  10
    How Are Identity Conditions Grounded?
    In Kanzian Christian (ed.), Persistence, Ontos. pp. 73-90. 2007.
  •  22
    Philosophy of language
    with Dominic Hyde
    Philosophical Books 44 (2): 174-178. 2003.
  • LYCAN, W.-Real Conditionals
    Philosophical Books 44 (2): 177-178. 2003.
  •  84
  •  15
    Understanding Identity Statements
    Philosophical Books 26 (4): 252-254. 1985.
  •  57
  •  5
    Editorials: Only Connect
    Philosophy 64 (n/a): 433. 1989.
  •  114
    There are no easy problems of consciousness
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 2 (3): 266-71. 1995.
    This paper challenges David Chalmers' proposed division of the problems of consciousness into the `easy' ones and the `hard' one, the former allegedly being susceptible to explanation in terms of computational or neural mechanisms and the latter supposedly turning on the fact that experiential `qualia' resist any sort of functional definition. Such a division, it is argued, rests upon a misrepresention of the nature of human cognition and experience and their intimate interrelationship, thereby …Read more
  •  113
    Locke: Compatibilist event-causalist or libertarian substance-causalist? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (3). 2004.
    Towards the end of Chapter XXI of Book II of the Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke remarks, with all the appearance of sincerity and genuine modesty, that.
  • The Psychology of Freedom (review)
    Philosophy 73 (2): 305-324. 1998.
  •  51
  •  34
    Review of Maria Elisabeth Reicher (ed.), States of Affairs (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (10). 2009.
  •  63
    Self, Reference and Self-Reference
    Philosophy 68 (263): 15-33. 1993.
    I favour an analysis of selfhood which ties it to the possession of certain kinds of first-person knowledge, in particular de re knowledge of the identity of one's own conscious thoughts and experiences. My defence of this analysis will lead me to explore the nature of demonstrative reference to one's own conscious thoughts and experiences. Such reference is typically ‘direct’, in contrast to demonstrative reference to all physical objects, apart from those that are parts of one's own body in wh…Read more
  •  121
    Indirect perception and sense data
    Philosophical Quarterly 31 (October): 330-342. 1981.
  •  266
    An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind
    Cambridge University Press. 2000.
    In this book Jonathan Lowe offers a lucid and wide-ranging introduction to the philosophy of mind. Using a problem-centred approach designed to stimulate as well as instruct, he begins with a general examination of the mind-body problem and moves on to detailed examination of more specific philosophical issues concerning sensation, perception, thought and language, rationality, artificial intelligence, action, personal identity and self-knowledge. His discussion is notably broad in scope, and di…Read more
  •  236
    Categorial predication
    Ratio 25 (4): 369-386. 2012.
    When, for example, we say of something that it ‘is an object’, or ‘is an event’, or ‘is a property’, we are engaging in categorial predication: we are assigning something to a certain ontological category. Ontological categorization is clearly a type of classification, but it differs radically from the types of classification that are involved in the taxonomic practices of empirical sciences, as when a physicist says of a certain particle that it ‘is an electron’, or when a zoologist says of a c…Read more
  •  284
    The definition of endurance
    Analysis 69 (2): 277-280. 2009.
    David Lewis, following in the tradition of Broad, Quine and Goodman, says that change in an object X consists in X's being temporally extended and having qualitatively different temporal parts. Analogously, change in a spatially extended object such as a road consists in its having different spatial parts . The alternative to this view is that ordinary objects undergo temporal change in virtue of having different intrinsic non-relational properties at different times. They endure, remaining the …Read more