•  22
    Philosophy of language
    with Dominic Hyde
    Philosophical Books 44 (2): 174-178. 2003.
  •  22
    Objects and criteria of identity
    In R. Hole & C. Wright (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Blackwell. 1997.
    'Object' and 'criterion of identity' are philosophical terms of art whose application lies at a considerable theoretical remove from the surface phenomena of everyday linguistic usage. This partly explains their highly controversial status, for their point of application lies precisely where the concerns of linguists and philosophers of language merge with those of metaphysicians. This chapter explains the possession of determinate identity‐conditions. It argues that the distinction between 'abs…Read more
  •  21
    A Serious Look at Serious Naturalism (review)
    Philosophia Christi 4 (1): 197-202. 2002.
  •  21
    Abstract Particulars
    Philosophical Quarterly 41 (162): 104-106. 1991.
  •  21
    Recent advances in metaphysics
    Facta Philosophica 5 (1): 3-24. 2003.
  •  21
    The four-category ontology: reply to Kistler
    Analysis 64 (2): 152-157. 2004.
  •  20
    Why Is There Anything At All?
    with Peter van Inwagen
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 70 (Supplementary): 95-120. 1996.
  •  20
    The Intelligibility of Nature
    Philosophical Books 27 (4): 234-236. 1986.
  •  19
    Noonan On Naming And Predicating
    Analysis 46 (June): 159. 1986.
  •  19
    Locke: Compatibilist Event‐Causalist or Libertarian Substance‐Causalist? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (3): 688-701. 2004.
    Towards the end of Chapter XXI of Book II of the Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke remarks, with all the appearance of sincerity and genuine modesty, that.
  •  18
    Against disjunctivism
    In Adrian Haddock & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, Action, Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 95--111. 2008.
  •  16
    Substance, Identity and Time
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 (1): 61-100. 1988.
  •  16
    Not a counterexample to modus ponens
    Analysis 46 (4): 44-47. 1986.
  •  16
    Some Formal Ontological Relations
    Dialectica 58 (3): 297-316. 2004.
    Some formal ontological relations are identified, in the context of an account of ontological categorization. It is argued that neither formal ontological relations nor ontological categories should themselves be regarded as elements of being, but that this does not undermine the claim of formal ontology to be a purely objective science. It is also argued that some formal ontological relations, like some ontological categories, are more basic than others. A four‐category ontology is proposed, in…Read more
  •  15
    A possibilidade da metafísica
    Critica -. 2008.
  •  15
    Understanding Identity Statements
    Philosophical Books 26 (4): 252-254. 1985.
  •  15
    The Nature of True Minds
    Philosophical Books 35 (1): 56-57. 1994.
  •  15
    Review. Notes on philosophy, probability and mathematics. FP Ramsey (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (2): 300-301. 1997.
  •  14
    No Title available: REVIEWS
    Religious Studies 27 (3): 421-422. 1991.
  •  14
    The Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science
    Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 43 (1): 6-20. 2008.
  •  14
    European and American Philosophers
    with John Marenbon, Douglas Kellner, Richard D. Parry, Gregory Schufreider, Ralph McInerny, Andrea Nye, R. M. Dancy, Vernon J. Bourke, A. A. Long, James F. Harris, Thomas Oberdan, Paul S. MacDonald, Véronique M. Fóti, F. Rosen, James Dye, Pete A. Y. Gunter, Lisa J. Downing, W. J. Mander, Peter Simons, Maurice Friedman, Robert C. Solomon, Nigel Love, Mary Pickering, Andrew Reck, Simon J. Evnine, Iakovos Vasiliou, John C. Coker, Georges Dicker, James Gouinlock, Paul J. Welty, Gianluigi Oliveri, Jack Zupko, Tom Rockmore, Wayne M. Martin, Ladelle McWhorter, Hans-Johann Glock, Georgia Warnke, John Haldane, Joseph S. Ullian, Steven Rieber, David Ingram, Nick Fotion, George Rainbolt, Thomas Sheehan, Gerald J. Massey, Barbara D. Massey, David E. Cooper, David Gauthier, James M. Humber, J. N. Mohanty, Michael H. Dearmey, Oswald O. Schrag, Ralf Meerbote, George J. Stack, John P. Burgess, Paul Hoyningen-Huene, Nicholas Jolley, Adriaan T. Peperzak, William D. Richardson, Stephen Mulhall, and C.
    In Robert L. Arrington (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophers, Blackwell. 2017.
    Peter Abelard (1079–1142 ce) was the most wide‐ranging philosopher of the twelfth century. He quickly established himself as a leading teacher of logic in and near Paris shortly after 1100. After his affair with Heloise, and his subsequent castration, Abelard became a monk, but he returned to teaching in the Paris schools until 1140, when his work was condemned by a Church Council at Sens. His logical writings were based around discussion of the “Old Logic”: Porphyry's Isagoge, aristotle'S Categ…Read more
  •  13
    In Defense of Moderate‐Sized Specimens of Dry Goods
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 67 (3): 704-710. 2003.
  •  13
    Sameness and substance renewed
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (2): 456--461. 2005.
  •  13
    Why Is There Anything At All?
    Aristotelian Society Proceedings Supplement 70 111-120. 1996.
  •  12
    The 3D/4D Controversy: A Storm in a Teacup
    Noûs 40 (3): 570-578. 2006.
  •  12
    Non‐Cartesian Substance Dualism
    In Jonathan J. Loose, Angus John Louis Menuge & J. P. Moreland (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Substance Dualism, Wiley-blackwell. 2018.
    Non‐Cartesian substance dualism is a position in the philosophy of mind concerning the nature of the mind‐body relation or, more exactly, the person‐body relation. Whereas Cartesian substance dualism takes subjects of experience to be necessarily immaterial and indeed nonphysical substances, non‐Cartesian substance dualism does not insist on this. This distinctive feature of non‐Cartesian substance dualism gives it certain advantages over Cartesian dualism, without compelling it to forfeit any o…Read more