-
1Does Corporate Political Advocacy Wrong Shareholders?Journal of Business Ethics 1-13. forthcoming.Corporations are increasingly taking stands on contentious social and political issues such as racial justice, abortion, and LGBTQ + rights. Critics of such corporate political advocacy often allege that it is incompatible with corporate obligations to shareholders. This essay argues that those critics are mistaken. More specifically, this essay examines whether corporate political advocacy violates two important rights of shareholders: The right to have the corporation managed in their interest…Read more
-
4Compelled Speech at Work: Employer Mobilization as a Threat to Employee Speech RightsPhilosophy of Management 1-17. forthcoming.Employers often encourage, incentivize, or even require their employees to engage in politics in a variety of ways. For example, employers often encourage employees to vote, press employees to support particular political candidates or policies, require employees to participate in political events, or ask employees to contact elected officials to advocate for the employer’s interests. Such practices are all forms of employer mobilization. This essay considers the threat that employer mobilizatio…Read more
-
Empiricism and normative ethics : what do the biology and the psychology of morality have to do with ethics?In Frans B. M. De Waal, Patricia Smith Churchland, Telmo Pievani & Stefano Parmigiani (eds.), Evolved Morality: The Biology and Philosophy of Human Conscience, Brill. 2014.
-
420LiberalismIn William A. Galston & Tom G. Palmer (eds.), Truth and Governance. pp. 193-215. 2021.Liberalism has a complicated and sometimes uneasy relationship with truth. On one hand, liberalism requires that truth be widely valued and widely shared. It demands that governments be truthful and that citizens have ready access to numerous truths. Some liberals even take facilitating the discovery and dissemination of truth to be part of the raison d’être of liberal institutions. On the other hand, liberalism is averse to proclaiming or enforcing truth. It detaches truth from political legit…Read more
-
35Bias, Safeguards, and the Limits of IndividualsBusiness Ethics Journal Review 10 (5): 27-32. 2022.The Radical Behavioral Challenge (RBC) contends that due to normal human cognitive biases, many standard prescriptions of business ethics run afoul of the principle that ‘ought implies can.’ Von Kriegstein responds to this challenge by arguing that those prescriptions are wide-scope obligations that can be fulfilled by recusing oneself or by establishing appropriate safeguards. I argue that this solution falls short of fully resolving the RBC because individuals will often be incapable of recogn…Read more
-
57Corporate CounterspeechEthical Theory and Moral Practice 26 (4): 611-625. 2023.Are corporations ever morally obligated to engage in counterspeech—that is, in speech that aims to counter hate speech and misinformation? While existing arguments in moral and political philosophy show that individuals and states have such obligations, it is an open question whether those arguments apply to corporations as well. In this essay, I show how two such arguments—one based on avoiding complicity, and one based on duties of rescue—can plausibly be extended to corporations. I also respo…Read more
-
73How to Allow Conscientious Objection in Medicine While Protecting Patient RightsCambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (1): 120-131. 2017.
-
91The Fact of Unreasonable PluralismJournal of the American Philosophical Association 5 (4): 410-428. 2019.Proponents of political liberalism standardly assume that the citizens of an ideal liberal society would be overwhelmingly reasonable. I argue that this assumption violates political liberalism's own constraints of realism—constraints that are necessary to frame the central problem that political liberalism aims to solve, that is, the problem of reasonable pluralism. To be consistent with these constraints, political liberalism must recognize that, as with reasonable pluralism, widespread suppor…Read more
-
70Political irrationality, utopianism, and democratic theoryPolitics, Philosophy and Economics 19 (1): 3-21. 2020.People tend to be biased and irrational about politics. Should this constrain what our normative theories of democracy can require? David Estlund argues that the answer is ‘no’. He contends that even if such facts show that the requirements of a normative theory are very unlikely to be met, this need not imply that the theory is unduly unrealistic. I argue that the application of Estlund’s argument to political irrationality depends on a false presupposition: mainly, that being rational about po…Read more
-
50The need for feasible compromises on conscientious objection: response to CardJournal of Medical Ethics 45 (8): 560-561. 2019.Robert Card criticises our proposal for managing some conscientious objections in medicine. Unfortunately, he severely mischaracterises the nature of our proposal, its scope and its implications. He also overlooks the fact that our proposal is a compromise designed for a particular political context. We correct Card’s mischaracterisations, explain why we believe compromise is necessary and explain how we think proposed compromises should be evaluated.
-
105Empiricism and normative ethics: What do the biology and the psychology of morality have to do with ethics?Behaviour 151 (2-3). 2014.What do the biology and psychology of morality have to do with normative ethics? Our answer is, a great deal. We argue that normative ethics is an ongoing, ever-evolving research program in what is best conceived as human ecology.
-
50Democratic Theory for a Market Democracy: The Problem of Merriment and Diversion When Regulators and the Regulated MeetJournal of Social Philosophy 49 (4): 536-563. 2018.Democratic theorists, especially since the advent of the deliberative democracy paradigm in the 1980s, have focused primarily on relationships involving citizens and their political representatives, and have thus paid scant attention to the bureaucratic agencies within the modern state that are presumed merely to “flesh out,” implement, and enforce the decisions made by elected officials. This undertheorized space between markets and democratic decision making, in brief, is where corporations an…Read more
-
43Ethics & empiricism: what do the biology and the psychology of morality have to do with ethics?In Frans B. M. De Waal, Patricia Smith Churchland, Telmo Pievani & Stefano Parmigiani (eds.), Evolved Morality: The Biology and Philosophy of Human Conscience, Brill. pp. 73-92. 2014.What do the biology and psychology of morality have to do with normative ethics? Our answer is, a great deal.We argue that normative ethics is an ongoing, ever-evolving research program in what is best conceived as human ecology.
-
150Democracy isn't that smart : On landemore's democratic reasonEpisteme 14 (2): 161-175. 2017.In her recent book, Democratic Reason, Hélène Landemore argues that, when evaluated epistemically, “a democratic decision procedure is likely to be a better decision procedure than any non-democratic decision procedures, such as a council of experts or a benevolent dictator” (p. 3). Landemore's argument rests heavily on studies of collective intelligence done by Lu Hong and Scott Page. These studies purport to show that cognitive diversity – differences in how people solve problems – is actually…Read more
Aaron J. Ancell
Bentley University
-
Bentley UniversityAssistant Professor
Waltham, MA, United States of America