•  846
    Plain sex
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 6 (3): 267-287. 1977.
  •  519
    What we learn about rules from the cider house rules
    Philosophy and Literature 34 (2): 359-372. 2010.
    In a well known collection of essays, Martha Nussbaum has argued that novels are indispensable in teaching and learning ethics in the right way.1 A large part of such learning consists in developing the capacity to perceive and respond to complex, nuanced situations having numerous morally relevant features deriving from particular relationships and past commitments that combine these context sensitive features in unique and unpredictable ways. Careful attention to detailed, intricate stories wi…Read more
  •  501
    Aesthetic qualities and aesthetic value
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (1): 23-37. 1990.
    To say that an object is beautiful or ugly is seemingly to refer to a property of the object. But it is also to express a positive or negative response to it, a set of aesthetic values, and to suggest that others ought to respond in the same way. Such judg- ments are descriptive, expressive, and normative or prescriptive at once. These multiple features are captured well by Humean accounts that analyze the judgments as ascribing relational properties. To say that an object is beautiful is to say…Read more
  •  439
    The entitlement theory of distributive justice
    Journal of Philosophy 73 (21): 823-835. 1976.
  •  368
    Business ethics: Profits, utilities, and moral rights
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 9 (3): 260-286. 1980.
  •  311
    Huckleberry Finn and moral motivation
    Philosophy and Literature 34 (1). 2010.
    Huckleberry Finn is not irrational in being unmotivated to follow his explicit judgments of rightness and wrongness. Philosophers have previously judged Huck to be irrational, subject to weakness of will, in being unable to act on his moral judgment. But their interpretation rests on incorrect analyses of weak will and of the emotions on which Huck does act. I also argue that such emotion based motivation is not of the kind that could be rationally required. The character of Huckleberry Finn the…Read more
  •  245
  •  218
    The moral foundations of professional ethics (edited book)
    Rowman & Littlefield. 1980.
    This books examines the fundamental values and principles of conduct in the professions, focusing specifically on four areas: law, politics, medicine and business. One central question unifies its inquiry into the different professions: should the principles for judging the actions of professionals be the same as those used to judge private individuals, or do these professions require special moral principles to guide their conduct. The author considers arguments deriving from the underlying ins…Read more
  •  212
    Realism about aesthetic properties
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 51 (1): 31-37. 1993.
  •  208
    Aesthetic value
    Westview Press. 1995.
    In this concise survey, intended for advanced undergraduate students of aesthetics, Alan Goldman focuses on the question of aesthetic value, using many practical examples from painting, music, and literature to make his case. Although he treats a wide variety of views, he argues for a nonrealist view of aesthetic value, showing that the personal element can never be factored out of evaluative aesthetic judgments and explaining why this is so.
  •  192
  •  176
    Appearing as irreducible in perception
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 37 (December): 147-164. 1976.
  •  159
    Interpreting art and literature
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 48 (3): 205-214. 1990.
  •  147
    Affirmative action
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 5 (2): 178-195. 1976.
  •  142
    The value of music
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1): 35-44. 1992.
  •  131
    Toward a new theory of punishment
    Law and Philosophy 1 (1). 1982.
    Criteria for a successful theory of punishment include first, that it specify a reasonable limit to punishments in particular cases, and second, that it allow benefits to outweigh costs in a penal institution.It is argued that traditional utilitarian and retributive theories fail to satisfy both criteria, and that they cannot be coherently combined so as to do so. Retributivism specifies a reasonable limit in its demand that punishment equal crime, but this limit fails to allow benefits to outwe…Read more
  •  127
    The education of taste
    British Journal of Aesthetics 30 (2): 105-116. 1990.
  •  123
  •  114
    The aesthetic value of representation in painting
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2): 297-310. 1995.
  •  111
    Desire, depression, and rationality
    Philosophical Psychology 20 (6). 2007.
    Internalists hold that all reasons derive from existing motivations. They also hold that agents act irrationally when they fail to act on the strongest reasons they have. Emotions can make one act irrationally. But depression as an emotion tends to remove the motivation to act at the same time as it causes irrational inaction. If depression can cause irrationality, then the reasons to act must remain. Hence the internalist must explain how reasons can remain if depression removes motivation. Thi…Read more
  •  108
    The Broad View of Aesthetic Experience
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 71 (4): 323-333. 2013.
    Peter Kivy and Noël Carroll advocate a narrow view of aesthetic experience according to which it consists mainly in attention to formal properties. Excluded are cognitive and moral properties. I defend the broader view that includes the latter properties. I argue first that cognition and moral assessment can be inseparable in experience from grasp of form and expressiveness. Second, Kivy and Carroll must extend the notion of form itself beyond ordinary usage to accommodate acknowledged aesthetic…Read more
  •  101
    Beardsley's legacy: The theory of aesthetic value
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 63 (2). 2005.
    Alan Goldman; Beardsley's Legacy: The Theory of Aesthetic Value: Symposium: Monroe Beardsley's Legacy in Aesthetics, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism.
  •  95
    Realism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 17 (2): 175-192. 1979.
    Definitions of stronger and weaker versions of physical realism are offered, The first relating to the existence of physical objects and the second to the independence of their properties. It is argued that recent debates about the commensurability and convergence of scientific theories and the causal theory of reference are irrelevant to the truth of these theses, Although their proponents seem to think them linked. It is then argued that support for realist positions must be inductive. Such su…Read more
  •  93
    Red and right
    Journal of Philosophy 84 (7): 349-362. 1987.
  •  89
    Reasons from within: desires and values
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    Alan H. Goldman argues for the internalist or subjectivist view of practical reasons on the grounds that it is simpler, more unified, and more comprehensible ...
  •  88
    Reply to Gould and Levinson on aesthetic realism
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 52 (3): 354-356. 1994.
  •  88
    What desires are, and are not
    Philosophical Studies 174 (2): 333-352. 2017.
    This paper criticizes the account of desire defended by Nomy Arpaly and Timothy Schroeder in their recent book, In Praise of Desire. It contrasts their account with one that I favor, a cluster analysis listing various criteria that are together sufficient for having paradigm desires, but none of which is necessary or sufficient for desiring. I argue that their account fails to state necessary or sufficient conditions, that it is explanatorily weaker than the cluster account, that it fails to pro…Read more