•  10
    Comments on “The Impossibility of Hypocritical Advice”
    Southwest Philosophy Review 39 (2): 79-83. 2023.
  •  9
    Killing and Letting Die
    In R. G. Frey & Christopher Heath Wellman (eds.), A Companion to Applied Ethics, Blackwell. 2005.
  •  196
    Torturing Puppies and Eating Meat
    Southwest Philosophy Review 20 (1): 117-123. 2004.
  •  17
    Letters to the Editor
    with Anto Knezevic, Frank B. Dilley, C. Tabor Fisher, Eric Hoffman, Thomas Urban, Dick Howard, Adrian Kuzminski, and William J. Massicotte
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 67 (6). 1994.
  • Two dogmas of deontology : aggregation, rights, and the separateness of persons
    In Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred Dycus Miller & Jeffrey Paul (eds.), Utilitarianism: the aggregation question, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
  •  4
    Killing and Letting Die (edited book)
    with Bonnie Steinbock
    Fordham University Press. 1994.
    This collection contains twenty-one thought-provoking essays on the controversies surrounding the moral and legal distinctions between euthanasia and "letting die." Since public awareness of this issue has increased this second edition includes nine entirely new essays which bring the treatment of the subject up-to-date. The urgency of this issue can be gauged in recent developments such as the legalization of physician-assisted suicide in the Netherlands, "how-to" manuals topping the bestseller…Read more
  •  213
    The Impotence of the Causal Impotence Objection
    Southwest Philosophy Review 36 (1): 161-168. 2020.
    Many significant harms, such as the mass suffering of animals on factory farms, can only be prevented, or at least lessened, by the collective action of thousands, or in some cases millions, of individual agents. In the face of this, it can seem as if individuals are powerless to make a difference, and thus that they lack reasons, at least from the consequentialist perspective, to refrain from eating meat. This has become known as the “causal impotence” problem. The standard response is to appea…Read more
  •  51
    Morality by Degrees: Reasons Without Demands
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    Alastair Norcross argues that the basic judgments of morality are essentially comparative: alternatives are judged to be better or worse than each other. Notions such as right and wrong are not part of the fundamental subject matter of moral theory, but are constructed in a context-relative fashion out of the basic comparative judgments.
  •  1
    Moral Conflicts and Moral Psychology
    Dissertation, Syracuse University. 1991.
    I examine several claims about the nature of values that have been made with respect to moral conflict, i.e., that the existence of moral conflict shows that values are incomparable; values are incommensurable but comparable; there are plural values. ;Strong moral conflicts involve an agent in a choice between two or more impermissible alternatives. They have been thought to pose serious problems for ethical theories, in particular for consequentialist theories. According to consequentialist eth…Read more
  •  122
    Contractualism and Aggregation
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (2): 303-314. 2002.
  •  3
    Scalar ActUtilitarianism
    In Henry West (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 217. 2008.
  •  50
    Death for animals
    In Jens Johansson Fred Feldman Ben Bradley (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Death, . pp. 465. 2013.
  •  15
    Why Legitimacy Doesn’t Entail Obligation
    Southwest Philosophy Review 26 (2): 13-16. 2010.
  •  24
    Contractualism and Aggregation
    Social Theory and Practice 28 (2): 303-314. 2002.
  •  115
    Harming In Context
    Philosophical Studies 123 (1-2): 149-173. 2005.
  •  102
    Contextualism for consequentialists
    Acta Analytica 20 (2): 80-90. 2005.
    If, as I have argued elsewhere, consequentialism is not fundamentally concerned with such staples of moral theory as rightness, duty, obligation, moral requirements, goodness (as applied to actions), and harm, what, if anything, does it have to say about such notions? While such notions have no part to play at the deepest level of the theory, they may nonetheless be of practical significance. By way of explanation I provide a linguistic contextualist account of these notions. A contextualist app…Read more
  •  532
    “The Scalar Approach to Utilitarianism”
    In Henry West (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 217--32. 2008.
    This chapter contains section titled: Introduction The Demandingness Objection Scalar Utilitarianism Wrongness as Blameworthiness Rightness and Goodness as Guides to Action.
  •  21
    Rational Rouletie
    Southwest Philosophy Review 12 (1): 191-196. 1996.
  •  66
    Moral Intuitions and fMRI Research
    Southwest Philosophy Review 25 (2): 19-23. 2009.
  •  171
    Good and bad actions
    Philosophical Review 106 (1): 1-34. 1997.
    It is usually assumed to be possible, and sometimes even desirable, for consequentialists to make judgments about both the rightness and the goodness of actions. Whether a particular action is right or wrong is one question addressed by a consequentialist theory such as utilitarianism. Whether the action is good or bad, and how good or bad it is, are two others. I will argue in this paper that consequentialism cannot provide a satisfactory account of the goodness of actions, on the most natural …Read more
  •  36
    Was Mill an “India House” Utilitarian?
    Southwest Philosophy Review 23 (2): 1-4. 2007.
  •  113
    Consequentialism and commitment
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (4). 1997.
    It is sometimes claimed that a consequentialist theory such as utilitarianism has problems accommodating the importance of personal commitments to other people. However, by emphasizing the distinction between criteria of rightness and decision procedures, a consequentialist can allow for non-consequentialist decision procedures, such as acting directly on the promptings of natural affection. Furthermore, such non-consequentialist motivational structures can co-exist happily with a commitment to …Read more
  •  60
  •  90
    A Consequentialist Case for Rejecting the Right
    Journal of Philosophical Research 18 109-125. 1993.
    Satisficing and maximizing versions of consequentialism have both assumed that rightness is an alI-or-nothing property. We argue thal this is inimical to the spirit of consequentialism, and that, from the point of view of the consequentialist, actions should be evaluated purely in terms that admit of degree. We first consider the suggestion that rightness and wrongness are a matter of degree. If so, this raises the question of whether the claim that something is wrong says any more than that it …Read more
  •  35
    Peacemaking Philosophy or Appeasement? Sterba’s Argument for Compromise
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 19 (2): 285-296. 2005.
    In The Triumph of Practice over Theory in Ethics James Sterba is not concerned merely to show that there is much convergence in the practical application of Utilitarianism, Kantianism, and Aristotelian virtue ethics. His project is the much more ambitious one of arguing that the theories do not really diverge very much at the theoretical level, and thus supplying an explanation for the apparent convergence at the practical level. Although I applaud him for the boldness, some might even say audac…Read more
  •  53
    Intending and Foreseeing Death
    Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1): 115-123. 1999.