Introduction Basic Emotion Theory proper (BET) has only recently begun to make an appearance in musical research (see Juslin, 1998; 2013a&b). However, much theory and research in music psychology has been driven by a more general assumption that musical emotions should be investigated in terms of discrete ad-hoc categories associated with the ways specific neural mechanisms respond to musical stimuli (see Schiavio et al., 2016). This has been problematized, however, by studies that show that the…
Read moreIntroduction Basic Emotion Theory proper (BET) has only recently begun to make an appearance in musical research (see Juslin, 1998; 2013a&b). However, much theory and research in music psychology has been driven by a more general assumption that musical emotions should be investigated in terms of discrete ad-hoc categories associated with the ways specific neural mechanisms respond to musical stimuli (see Schiavio et al., 2016). This has been problematized, however, by studies that show that the physiological changes associated with musical emotions do not always align clearly with those exhibited in association with everyday emotion categories (Krumhansl, 1997, p. 351; Scherer & Zentner, 2001). Such concerns have led some scholars to posit that musical emotions may be somehow different (or perhaps ‘impoverished’) versions of real emotions (Sloboda, 2000). In response to this, other researchers (e.g., Scherer & Couthino, 2014) have developed models that do away with the notion of basic emotions altogether, preferring instead to describe emotional reactions to music in terms of complex information processing components that combine in various ways to produce relevant outputs (see also Huron, 2006). Still others (Krueger, 2013; Schiavio et al., 2016; van der Schyff, 2013; see also Koelsch, 2013) have suggested that reducing musical experience to a stimulus-response framework - where emotions are thought to be caused in listeners by pre-given stimuli in the environment - may play down the active and creative role living embodied agents play in musical experience.With this in mind, we offer below a brief critique of BET, suggesting that it may not in fact provide the best way forward for research in musical emotions. We then outline an alternative perspective, drawing on research that employs dynamical systems theory (DST) (Colombetti, 2014; Lewis & Granic, 2000). To conclude, we offer some preliminary suggestions for how this approach might be applied in musical contexts. Before we begin, it should be noted that musical research that draws on the idea of ‘basic emotions’ has indeed produced important insights. Such studies are carried out in controlled settings that adhere to high scientific research standards - they offer important sources of data that will have to be taken into consideration by any alternative theoretical orientation. To be clear, then, our aim is not to debunk or discredit the work of researchers endorsing BET. Rather, our goal is simply to outline another perspective that could make important contributions to the dialogue. Basic emotions In folk psychology, the notion of ‘basic emotions’ involves the assumption that emotions come in a group of pre-defined categories such as happy, sad, angry and so on. This idea has been formalized by Basic Emotion Theory (BET) proper, which claims the existence of a small group of ‘discrete’ basic emotions that evolved in response to the challenges our ancestors faced in their everyday life (Ekman, 1980). It is argued that each basic emotion is defined by a dedicated (innate and distinct) neural network, which controls the ‘affect programs’ that give rise to them (Tomkins, 1962, 1963; see also Colombetti, 2014). Here the term ‘affect programs’ refers to the mechanisms that produce “the patterns for these complex organized responses, and which when set off directs their occurrence” (Ekman, 1980a p., 82). Such programs and the responses they trigger (i.e., basic emotions) are thought to be culturally universal and are thus understood to function as “auto appraisals” selected by evolution (Ekman, 1999; Ekman, 2003; Ekman & Friesen, 1971, 1986). It has also been suggested that because of the supposed categorical fixity of these basic emotions, they might form the ‘building blocks’ from which more complex emotions emerge (Prinz, 2004a&b).Some critics have raised the question of how, precisely, alleged basic emotions relate to non-basic ones (Ortony & Turner, 1990). And there is an ongoing debate between those who argue that basic and non-basic emotions are continuous (Clark, 2010; Plutchick, 2001; Prinz, 2004a&b), and those who insist that the two involve distinct processes and should thus be studied separately (Damasio, 1994; LeDoux, 1996). Other authors question BET’s lack of context sensitivity (Barrett, 2006; Russell, 2003): emotions can be expressed and experienced in various ways and their meanings shift depending on the situation. Still others have drawn attention to the BET methodology, which often employs a forced choice approach (generally between facial expressions and a given scenario). Indeed, research has shown that quite different responses may be given when participants are not constrained by emotional labelling (Russell, 1994). It has also been pointed out that the close correlations that are expected to occur between specific brain areas, autonomic nervous system activity, and the putative affect programs associated with basic emotions are often less consistent than hypothesized (Barrett, 2006). While advocates of BET have responded to such criticisms in various ways (e.g., Ekman & Cordaro, 2011), another more general problem remains concerning the rather arbitrary way basic emotion categories were originally introduced. To be clear, all of this does not negate the observation that emotional episodes involve recurring psycho-physical patterns of behavior that are indeed nameable, and that may bear striking similarities across individuals and groups. Rather, it suggests that we need to develop new approaches for studying such phenomena.Emotions as dynamic and emergentResearch based on DST suggests that emotional episodes may not be reducible to pre-given response mechanisms in the brain, but rather emerge through developmental processes spanning an integrated body-brain-environment network (Freeman, 2000; Lewis, 2000; 2005). Colombetti (2014, pp. 57-82) suggests three mutually informing levels of inquiry that may help us better understand how this is so. The first of these involves the development of the muscular linkages and coordinative structures associated with emotional expression (e.g., facial, vocal, limb, and hand movement). And indeed, research shows that the appearance of recurrent and meaningful patterns of expressive behavior in infants is not best understood wholly in terms of predetermined (i.e., genetic) developmental programs, but rather as emergent properties of the dynamic interaction of a range of environmental and bodily factors (Camras & Witherington, 2005; Fogel & Thelen, 1987). The second level draws on existing work in affective neuroscience that highlights the plasticity and self-organizing nature of neural structures (see Freeman, 1999; 2000). Here, emotional episodes are explored as patterns of convergence (basins of attraction) in the neural trajectories of an agent that may both stabilize and transform due to contingent shifts in the global constraints of the brain-body-world system. The third level focusses on environmental concerns, exploring how agents enact meaningful emotional engagements (i.e., recurrent patterns of relational behavior) with the things and people they interact with, and the situations they live through (Hsu & Fogel, 2003; Laible & Thompson, 2000). From this perspective, emotional episodes are not limited to the skull or the skin of the organism. There is, rather, a strong sense in which they ‘extend’ (Krueger, 2014; Krueger & Szanto, 2016; Slaby, 2014) into environments where agents co-enact meaningful worlds through forms of participatory sense-making (such as music; see Schiavio & De Jaegher, 2017). In brief, the DST approach explores the active and self-organizing nature of emotional experience as it develops across bodily, neural, and ecological dimensions, suggesting that while emotional episodes can indeed be unique to an individual organism, they may also emerge in ways that are shared between agents with similar biological/social needs and histories of interaction with the environment. Exploring the dynamics of musical emotionsIt should be noted that work in music cognition has already begun to develop DST approaches. For example, researchers (e.g., Large & Jones, 1999) have investigated how the neural dynamics associated with musical experience actively resonate and self-organize with those of the body and the environment in a recursive or ‘circular’ way. However, such ‘dynamic attending’ to music has been explored mostly in the context of rhythmic entrainment and pitch perception (e.g., Large et al., 2016; see also McGrath & Kelly, 1986). We suggest that future research could develop the emotional implications of this more fully. Indeed, this would contribute to a larger body of inter-disciplinary work that explores the creative, social, embodied, ecological, and developmental aspects of musical experience (DeNora, 2000; Leman, 2007; van der Schyff, 2015). For example, it has been shown that even in contexts that appear to be ‘passive’ (e.g., listening in a concert hall) people play active roles in shaping their engagements with musical environments (Clarke, 2005; Krueger, 2014) - e.g., by developing ‘metaphorical’, cross-modal, and ‘narrative’ relationships between various temporal, spatial, textural, bodily, social, ecological, and affective dimensions (see Johnson, 2005). Here, DST could be useful for exploring how such experiences are enacted, especially when integrated with phenomenological descriptions. This orientation could also be developed in contexts involving the production of music (performance, rehearsal, instrumental practice, and so on). Indeed, because musical performance clearly involves the integration of the three levels of description discussed above (bodily/neural/environmental), DST might be used to investigate and describe situations where two or more individuals participate in realizing the same musical event. This could involve the use of electrophysiological measurements in association with techniques such as functional near-infrared spectroscopy (fNIRS), which are increasingly adopted in the context of social cognition (Osaka et al., 2015; Pu et al., 2016). As fNIRS allows for the measurement of hemodynamic activities in participatory settings it could be particularly useful for exploring music-related activities in terms of interpersonal emotional dynamics. These could be analyzed in conjunction with audio and video recordings (to help capture sonic, bodily, and other environmental aspects); as well as through interviews with the participants to better understand how various forms of musically adaptive behavior might initiate (and be driven by) emotional episodes that are both recurrent and new, and how such episodes are experienced by the participants (e.g., as shared and/or as personal). Examples of similar data collection methods come from work by Walton and colleagues (2014; 2015) who have used DST to study perceptions of creativity in interacting musical improvisers (see also Borgo, 2005; Laroche & Kaddouch, 2015).In all, we suggest that a DST approach may better capture the (inter)active ways people enact emotional relationships with music, and how such experiences develop diachronically. That is, it may help us better understand how musical emotions emerge and transform developmentally in the context of people’s lives - where stable or recurrent patterns of behavior may come to be experienced in similar ways between embodied agents, and thus be subject to ‘loose’ labelling without being wholly pre-determined, fixed, or simply reducible to discrete categories. Likewise, it may also provide insights into the more idiosyncratic ways we engage emotionally with music – e.g., the conscious ways individuals seek out new approaches to music making as a means of creative expression, or as a way of enacting meaningful but highly personal embodied-emotional relationships (aesthetic, social, therapeutic) with the environments they inhabit (DeNora, 2000). ConclusionWhile BET-based approaches will continue to provide many useful insights in more controlled environments, we suggest that the DST perspective may better capture the manifold ways emotional engagement with music unfolds in the complex, embodied, and socially interactive contexts that characterize lived experience. Because this approach sees emotions as emergent and enacted, and not first in terms of pre-given categories or ‘affect programs’, it arguably sidesteps the problematic issue introduced above regarding whether musical emotions correspond with ‘basic’, ‘real’, or ‘everyday’ emotions. In line with this, it would be very interesting to see how the results of musical research that assume a basic emotion approach might be reinterpreted from a DST perspective. Additionally, DST might also shed light on important aspects of musical development in early childhood. Lastly, because DST-based research sees emotionality as inextricable from our embodied and social existence, it could have more general implications for areas such as music education and therapy - perhaps providing ways for teachers, students, therapists, and patients to better understand and discuss their engagements with music and its meaning for their lives.