•  5
    Starting with Kant
    Continuum. 2012.
    A new introduction to Kant, guiding the student through the key concepts of his work by examining the overall development of his ideas.
  •  51
    Immanuel Kants three critiques the Critique of Pure Reason, the Critique of Practical Reason and the Critique of Judgment are among the pinnacles of Western Philosophy. This accessible study grounds Kants philosophical position in the context of his intellectual influences, most notably against the background of the scepticism and empiricism of David Hume. It is an ideal critical introduction to Kants views in the key areas of knowledge and metaphysics; morality and freedom; and beauty and desig…Read more
  •  37
    Mental Representations and Intentional Behavior
    Southwest Philosophy Review 4 (1): 95-101. 1988.
  •  29
    Naturalism and the mental realm
    Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1): 157-167. 1999.
  •  9
    Values and Science
    Philosophy in the Contemporary World 8 (1): 67-80. 2001.
    This essay argues for a pragmatist notion of inquiry which ties together science and morality into a seamless whole, pace David Hume, Gilbert Harman, and others who would separate science and morality as different kinds of inquiry.
  •  172
    The Failure of Dennett’s Representationalism: A Wittgensteinian Resolution
    Journal of Philosophical Research 18 285-307. 1993.
    Jerry Fodor begins chapter one of The Language of Thought with two claims. The first claim is that “[T]he only psychological models of cognitive processes that seem remotely plausible represent such processes as computational.” The second claim is that “[C]omputation presupposes a medium of computation: a representational system.” Together these two claims suggest one of the central theses of many contemporary representationalist theories of mind, viz. that the only remotely plausible psychology…Read more
  •  44
    Scepticism, Truth and Pragmatic Inquiry
    Southwest Philosophy Review 17 (1): 159-172. 2000.
  •  7
    Putting Value into Art
    The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 1 177-182. 1998.
    The attempt to base a standard for assessing the value of works of art upon sentiment was famously made by David Hume in his essay "Of the Standard of Taste." Hume's attempt is generally regarded as fundamentally important in the project of explaining the nature of value judgements in the arts by means of an empirical, rather than a priori, relation. Recently, Hume's argument has been strongly criticized by Malcolm Budd in his book Values of Art. Budd contends that Hume utterly fails to show how…Read more
  •  7
    Proof and Demonstration
    International Philosophical Quarterly 48 (1): 23-37. 2008.
    On the standard reading of Hume, the belief that the necessity associated with the causal relation is “an entirely mind-independent phenomenon” in the world isunjustified. For example, Jonathan Bennett writes that necessary connections of the sort that Hume allows are not “relations which hold objectively between the ‘objects’ or events which we take to be causally related.” Similarly, Barry Stroud writes that, according to Hume, we believe falsely “that necessity is something that ‘resides’ in …Read more
  •  76
  •  43
    Hume, Demonstratives, and Self-Ascriptions of Identity
    Hume Studies 11 (1): 69-93. 1985.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:69 HUME, DEMONSTRATIVES, AND SELF-ASCRIPTIONS OF IDENTITY I. In his A Treatise of Human Nature1(hereafter referred to as the Treatise and, for purposes of citation, abbreviated as 'T'), Hume says that "[T]he identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man, is only a fictitious one..." (T 259) Although some commentators read this as tantamount to the claim that we can have no idea of a mind, this seems too strong. To see what Hume is ge…Read more
  •  67
    In their recent book, Is Inequality Bad for Our Health?, Daniels, Kennedy, and Kawachi claim that to “act justly in health policy, we must have knowledge about the causal pathways through which socioeconomic (and other) inequalities work to produce differential health outcomes.” One of the central problems with this approach is its dependency on “knowledge about the causal pathways.” A widely held belief is that the randomized clinical trial (RCT) is, and ought to be the “gold standard” of evalu…Read more
  •  13
    Hume and the problem of representation
    Philosophical Papers 17 (1): 61-76. 1988.
    No abstract
  •  21
    Has Kant Answered Hume’s Causal Scepticism?
    Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 14 193-198. 2018.
    Do Hume and Kant hold strongly divergent views about the causal principle, viz. the principle that every event or change of state in nature must have a cause? It has traditionally been held that they do, and on the ground that while Hume claims that there is no justification for the principle’s acceptance, Kant claims that the principle can be shown to be necessary for the possibility of experience. However, I argue that, on Hume’s account of how we come to believe in the existence of external o…Read more
  • Michael Polanyi's search for truth
    with John V. Apczynski, Robert B. Glassman, Steven Reiss, Amos Yong, Jacqueline R. Cameron, Rebecca Sachs Norris, and Holmes Rolston Iii
    Zygon. forthcoming.
  •  67
    “Spurious Correlations and Causal Inferences”
    Erkenntnis 78 (3): 699-712. 2013.
    The failure to recognize a correlation as spurious can lead people to adopt strategies to bring about a specific outcome that manipulate something other than a cause of the outcome. However, in a 2008 paper appearing in the journal Analysis, Bert Leuridan, Erik Weber and Maarten Van Dyck suggest that knowledge of spurious correlations can, at least sometimes, justify adopting a strategy aiming at bringing about some change. This claim is surprising and, if true, throws into question the claim of…Read more
  •  36
    Proof and Demonstration
    International Philosophical Quarterly 48 (1): 23-37. 2008.
    On the standard reading of Hume, the belief that the necessity associated with the causal relation is “an entirely mind-independent phenomenon” in the world isunjustified. For example, Jonathan Bennett writes that necessary connections of the sort that Hume allows are not “relations which hold objectively between the ‘objects’ or events which we take to be causally related.” Similarly, Barry Stroud writes that, according to Hume, we believe falsely “that necessity is something that ‘resides’ in …Read more
  •  29
    Scapegoating Under Scrutiny
    with Jill A. Brown and Ann C. Buchholtz
    Proceedings of the International Association for Business and Society 19 383-394. 2008.
    This paper develops and tests a model of fingerpointing behaviors that board members experience because of regulatory reforms. We present the partial results of a large study of 138 board members on 54 publicly traded boards in the United States. We found that recent governance reforms that mandate increased accountability of board members are associated with less board cohesion and thatlower board cohesion is associated with fingerpointing behaviors. These findings suggest that the stages of in…Read more
  •  91
    The Value of Genetic Fallacies
    Informal Logic 30 (1): 1-33. 2010.
    Since at least the 1938 publication of Hans Reichenbach’s Experience and Predication , there has been widespread agreement that, when discussing the beliefs that people have, it is important to distinguish contexts of discovery and contexts of justification. Traditionally, when one conflates the two contexts, the result is a “genetic fallacy”. This paper examines genealogical critiques and addresses the question of whether such critiques are fallacious and, if so, whether this vitiates their use…Read more
  •  2
    Issues in Workplace Accommodations for People with Disabilities
    with Paul Baker and Nathan Moon
    Philosophy for Business 67. 2011.