•  12
    Discrimination against men (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 59 119-120. 2012.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 97 (386): 295-299. 1988.
  •  42
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Inductive Scepticism and Experimental Reasoning in Moral Subjects in Hume's Philosophy Anne Jaap Jacobson According to its title page, Hume's Treatise Concerning HumanNature is An ATTEMPT to introduce the experimental Method ofReasoning INTO MORAL SUBJECTS."1 And from the first section onwards, Hume makes statements about the human mind which are given an unqualified generality;An Enquiry ConcerningHuman Understanding is marked by a …Read more
  •  56
    Discrimination against men
    The Philosophers' Magazine 59 (59): 119-120. 2012.
  •  95
    Hume's "other words" which follow his first definition of causality in the "enquiry" are standardly read as giving us a counterfactual conditional. I argue that a more accurate reading reveals them to constitute a factual conditional, One reflecting a temporal restriction implicit in the first definition. The other words, So understood, Tell us merely that a component of the relation defined in the first definition is symmetrical
  •  8
    Drawing on a wide range of resources, including the history of philosophy, her role as director of a cognitive neuroscience group, and her Wittgensteinian training at Oxford, Jacobson provides fresh views on representation, concepts, perception, action, emotion and belief.
  •  49
    Three Concerns about the Origins of Content
    Philosophia 43 (3): 625-638. 2015.
    In this paper I will present three reservations about the claims made by Hutto and Satnet. First of all, though TNOC is presented as drawing on teleological theories of mental content for a conception of Ur-Intentionaltiy, what is separated out after objectionable claims are removed from teleological accounts may not retain enough to give us directed intelligence. This problem raises a question about what we need in a naturalistic basis for an account of the mental. Secondly, I think that the au…Read more
  •  21
    Group membership: Who gets to decide?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 39. 2016.
    In this commentary, I focus on several problems that the authors' understanding of group identity raises: the legality of avoiding background diversity, the problem of effectively unshareable knowledge, the practical quality of some outcomes arrived at by groups with homogeneous backgrounds, and moral issues about fairness. I note also that much recent research challenges the view that background diversity is more likely to be a detriment than a benefit.
  •  7
    Philosophy on the brain (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 66 121-122. 2014.
  •  14
    A Problem for Naturalizing Epistemologies
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (4): 31-49. 1992.
  •  13
    A Problem for Causal Theories of Reasons and Rationalizations
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (3): 307-321. 1993.
  •  3
    Stephen Stich, The Fragmentation of Reason (review)
    Philosophy in Review 11 362-364. 1991.
  •  20
    Philosophy on the brain (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 66 121-122. 2014.
  •  9
    The Problem of Induction: What Is Hume’s Argument?”
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 68 (3/4): 265-284. 1987.
  •  37
    Going beyond the hype of recent fMRI "findings," this interdisciplinary collection examines such questions as: Do women and men have significantly different brains? Do women empathize, while men systematize? Is there a "feminine" ethics? What does brain research on intersex conditions tell us about sex and gender?
  •  57
    A problem for naturalizing epistemologies
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (4): 31-49. 1992.
    Every epistemological theory needs to be able to articulate some version of the following principle: If S's belief "q" is to make S's belief "p" justified (or is to make "p" something S knows), then "q" must possess some positive epistemic merit. This paper argues that naturalizing epistemologies do not have access to this principle. The central problem is that of providing a naturalistic account of the notion of a reason-for-which one believes while avoiding internalist commitments. The discuss…Read more
  •  38
    Tenure and the political autonomy of faculty inquiry
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (6): 579-580. 2006.
    This commentary discusses several problems with the target article by Ceci et al. First, the results admit of an alternative interpretation that undercuts the conclusion drawn. In addition, at a number of points, the research should be supplemented by examining situations in which there is no tenure-granting policy. Finally, 60% of the questions are concerned with whistle-blowing, but the issues involved in such cases make them much less relevant to the assessment of tenure than the authors supp…Read more
  •  59
    Empathy and Instinct: Cognitive Neuroscience and Folk Psychology
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (5): 467-482. 2009.
    Might we have an instinctive tendency to perform helpful actions? This paper explores a model under development in cognitive neuroscience that enables us to understand what instinctive, helpful actions might look like. The account that emerges puts some pressure on key concepts in the philosophical understanding of folk psychology. In developing the contrast, a notion of embodied beliefs is introduced; it arguably fits folk conceptions better than philosophical ones. One upshot is that Humean in…Read more
  •  66
    A problem for causal theories of reasons and rationalizations
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (3): 307-321. 1993.
    Is causation either necessary or sufficient (or both) to make a belief-desire pair the reason for which one acts? In this paper I argue in support of a negative answer to this question, and thus attempt to shift the burden of proof onto the causal theorists. I also provide an outline of a different account of reasons and rationalization. Motivating my inquiry is a concern to show that ordinary ascriptions of reasons are not hostage to future accounts of how the brain works
  •  39
    Introduction
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 1 (4): 357-366. 2002.
  •  116
  •  62
    What should a theory of vision look like?
    Philosophical Psychology 21 (5). 2008.
    This paper argues for two major revisions in the way philosophers standardly think of vision science and vision theories more generally. The first concerns mental representations and the second supervenience. The central result is that the way is cleared for an externalist theory of perception. The framework for such a theory has what are called Aristotelian representations as elements in processes the well-functioning of which is the principal object of a theory of vision.