•  72
    Epistemology and Radically Extended Cognition
    Episteme 12 (4): 459-478. 2015.
    This paper concerns the relationship between epistemology and radically extended cognition. Radically extended cognition (REC) – as advanced by Andy Clark and David Chalmers – is cognition that is partly located outside the biological boundaries of the cognizing subject. Epistemologists have begun to wonder whether REC has any consequences for theories of knowledge. For instance, while Duncan Pritchard suggests that REC might have implications for which virtue epistemology is acceptable, J. Adam…Read more
  •  1
    Knowledge First, (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
  •  230
    Pragmatic Encroachment and Belief-Desire Psychology
    with Jonathan Jenkins Ichikawa and Katherine Rubin
    Analytic Philosophy 53 (4): 327-343. 2012.
    We develop a novel challenge to pragmatic encroachment. The significance of belief-desire psychology requires treating questions about what to believe as importantly prior to questions about what to do; pragmatic encroachment undermines that priority, and therefore undermines the significance of belief-desire psychology. This, we argue, is a higher cost than has been recognized by epistemologists considering embracing pragmatic encroachment.
  •  231
    Hybrid Virtue Epistemology and the A Priori
    In Dylan Dodd & Elia Zardini (eds.), The A Priori: Its Significance, Sources, and Extent, Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
    How should we understand good philosophical inquiry? Ernest Sosa has argued that the key to answering this question lies with virtue-based epistemology. According to virtue-based epistemology, competences are prior to epistemic justification. More precisely, a subject is justified in having some type of belief only because she could have a belief of that type by exercising her competences. Virtue epistemology is well positioned to explain why, in forming false philosophical beliefs, agents are o…Read more
  •  163
    Knowledge First: Approaches in Epistemology and Mind (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
    'Knowledge-First' constitutes what is widely regarded as one of the most significant innovations in contemporary epistemology in the past 25 years. Knowledge-first epistemology is the idea that knowledge per se should not be analysed in terms of its constituent parts (e.g., justification, belief), but rather that these and other notions should be analysed in terms of the concept of knowledge. This volume features a substantive introduction and 13 original essays from leading and up-and-coming ph…Read more
  •  63
    Evaluating the extended mind
    Philosophical Issues 24 (1): 209-229. 2014.
    According to proponents of radically extended cognition, some cognition is located outside the boundaries of biological organisms. In this paper, I offer a new argument for a modest version of this view according to which some cognitive processes are radically extended. I do so by showing that features of a subject's environment—in particular, the pen and paper that a subject uses to solve complex mathematical problems—can have epistemic roles that are indicative of cognitive roles. I end the pa…Read more
  •  136
    Knowledge, Cognitive Achievement, and Environmental Luck
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 94 (4): 529-551. 2013.
    This article defends the view that knowledge is type-identical to cognitive achievement. I argue, pace Duncan Pritchard, that not only knowledge, but also cognitive achievement is incompatible with environmental luck. I show that the performance of cognitive abilities in environmental luck cases does not distinguish them from non-abilities per se. For this reason, although the cognitive abilities of the subject are exercised in environmental luck cases, they are not manifested in any relevant se…Read more
  •  95
    Representing as Adapting
    Acta Analytica 30 (1): 17-39. 2015.
    In this paper, I recommend a creature-level theory of representing. On this theory, a creature represents some entity just in case the creature adapts its behavior to that entity. Adapting is analyzed in terms of establishing new patterns of behavior. The theory of representing as adapting is contrasted with traditional causal and informational theories of mental representation. Moreover, I examine the theory in light of Putnam-Burge style externalism; I show that Putnam-Burge style externalism …Read more
  •  40
    Book Symposium: Truth as One and Many : Truth as One and Very Many
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 20 (1): 105-114. 2012.
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies, Volume 20, Issue 1, Page 105-114, February 2012
  •  627
    Thought-experiment intuitions and truth in fiction
    Philosophical Studies 142 (2). 2009.
    What sorts of things are the intuitions generated via thought experiment? Timothy Williamson has responded to naturalistic skeptics by arguing that thought-experiment intuitions are judgments of ordinary counterfactuals. On this view, the intuition is naturalistically innocuous, but it has a contingent content and could be known at best a posteriori. We suggest an alternative to Williamson's account, according to which we apprehend thought-experiment intuitions through our grasp on truth in fict…Read more
  •  786
    Varieties of cognitive achievement
    with J. Adam Carter and Katherine Rubin
    Philosophical Studies 172 (6): 1603-1623. 2015.
    According to robust virtue epistemology , knowledge is type-identical with a particular species of cognitive achievement. The identification itself is subject to some criticism on the grounds that it fails to account for the anti-luck features of knowledge. Although critics have largely focused on environmental luck, the fundamental philosophical problem facing RVE is that it is not clear why it should be a distinctive feature of cognitive abilities that they ordinarily produce beliefs in a way …Read more
  •  1004
    Knowledge: Value on the Cheap
    with J. Adam Carter and Katherine Rubin
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (2): 249-263. 2013.
    ABSTRACT: We argue that the so-called ‘Primary’ and ‘Secondary’ Value Problems for knowledge are more easily solved than is widely appreciated. Pritchard, for instance, has suggested that only virtue-theoretic accounts have any hopes of adequately addressing these problems. By contrast, we argue that accounts of knowledge that are sensitive to the Gettier problem are able to overcome these challenges. To first approximation, the Primary Value Problem is a problem of understanding how the propert…Read more
  •  924
    Knowledge and the value of cognitive ability
    with J. Adam Carter and Katherine Rubin
    Synthese 190 (17): 3715-3729. 2013.
    We challenge a line of thinking at the fore of recent work on epistemic value: the line (suggested by Kvanvig in The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding, 2003 and others) that if the value of knowledge is “swamped” by the value of mere true belief, then we have good reason to doubt its theoretical importance in epistemology. We offer a value-driven argument for the theoretical importance of knowledge—one that stands even if the value of knowledge is “swamped” by the value of true…Read more
  •  829
    Against swamping
    Analysis 72 (4): 690-699. 2012.
    The Swamping Argument – highlighted by Kvanvig (2003; 2010) – purports to show that the epistemic value of truth will always swamp the epistemic value of any non-factive epistemic properties (e.g. justification) so that these properties can never add any epistemic value to an already-true belief. Consequently (and counter-intuitively), knowledge is never more epistemically valuable than mere true belief. We show that the Swamping Argument fails. Parity of reasoning yields the disastrous conclusi…Read more
  •  157
    The rules of thought
    Oxford University Press. 2013.
    Ichikawa and Jarvis offer a new rationalist theory of mental content and defend a traditional epistemology of philosophy. They argue that philosophical inquiry is continuous with non-philosophical inquiry, and can be genuinely a priori, and that intuitions do not play an important role in mental content or the a priori.
  •  93
    The Dual Aspects Theory of Truth
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 42 (3-4): 209-233. 2012.
    Consider the following 'principles':2(Norm of Belief Schema) Necessarily, a belief of is correct (relative to some scenario) if and only if p (at that scenario) — where 'p' has the aforementioned content .(Generalized Norm of Belief) Necessarily, for all propositions , a belief of is correct (relative to some scenario) if and only if is true (at that scenario).Both 'principles' appear to capture the aim(s) of belief. (NBS) particularizes the aims to beliefs of distinct content-types. (GNB) gener…Read more
  •  11
    Review of Truth, by Alexis G. Burgess and John P. Burgess (review)
    Essays in Philosophy 14 (2): 328-334. 2013.
  •  1115
    Norms of intentionality: norms that don’t guide
    Philosophical Studies 157 (1): 1-25. 2012.
    More than ever, it is in vogue to argue that no norms either play a role in or directly follow from the theory of mental content. In this paper, I present an intuitive theory of intentionality (including a theory of mental content) on which norms are constitutive of the intentional properties of attitude and content in order to show that this trend is misguided. Although this theory of intentionality—the teleological theory of intentional representation—does involve a commitment to representatio…Read more
  •  457
    How do we know what's (metaphysically) possible and impossible? Arguments from Kripke and Putnam suggest that possibility is not merely a matter of (coherent) conceivability/imaginability. For example, we can coherently imagine that Hesperus and Phosphorus are distinct objects even though they are not possibly distinct. Despite this apparent problem, we suggest, nevertheless, that imagination plays an important role in an adequate modal epistemology. When we discover what is possible or what is …Read more
  •  191
    Belief without credence
    with J. Adam Carter and Katherine Rubin
    Synthese 193 (8): 2323-2351. 2016.
    One of the deepest ideological divides in contemporary epistemology concerns the relative importance of belief versus credence. A prominent consideration in favor of credence-based epistemology is the ease with which it appears to account for rational action. In contrast, cases with risky payoff structures threaten to break the link between rational belief and rational action. This threat poses a challenge to traditional epistemology, which maintains the theoretical prominence of belief. The cor…Read more