•  40
    Conference on Computability, Complexity and Randomness
    with Verónica Becher, C. T. Chong, Rod Downey, Noam Greenberg, Antonin Kucera, Steffen Lempp, Antonio Montalbán, Jan Reimann, and Stephen Simpson
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (4): 548-549. 2008.
  •  385
    Only Human: a book review of The Turing Guide (review)
    Notices of the American Mathematical Society 66 (4). forthcoming.
    This is a review of The Turing Guide (2017), written by Jack Copeland, Jonathan Bowen, Mark Sprevak, Robin Wilson, and others. The review includes a new sociological approach to the problem of computability in physics.
  •  16
    Is there a nontrivial automorphism of the Turing degrees? It is a major open problem of computability theory. Past results have limited how nontrivial automorphisms could possibly be. Here we consider instead how an automorphism might be induced by a function on reals, or even by a function on integers. We show that a permutation of ω cannot induce any nontrivial automorphism of the Turing degrees of members of 2ω, and in fact any permutation that induces the trivial automorphism must be computa…Read more
  •  147
    Higher kurtz randomness
    with André Nies, Frank Stephan, and Liang Yu
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (10): 1280-1290. 2010.
    A real x is -Kurtz random if it is in no closed null set . We show that there is a cone of -Kurtz random hyperdegrees. We characterize lowness for -Kurtz randomness as being -dominated and -semi-traceable
  •  40
    Superhighness
    with Andrée Nies
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 50 (4): 445-452. 2009.
    We prove that superhigh sets can be jump traceable, answering a question of Cole and Simpson. On the other hand, we show that such sets cannot be weakly 2-random. We also study the class $superhigh^\diamond$ and show that it contains some, but not all, of the noncomputable K-trivial sets
  •  19
    Covering the recursive sets
    with Frank Stephan and Sebastiaan A. Terwijn
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 168 (4): 804-823. 2017.
  •  34
    Local initial segments of the Turing degrees
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 (1): 26-36. 2003.
    Recent results on initial segments of the Turing degrees are presented, and some conjectures about initial segments that have implications for the existence of nontrivial automorphisms of the Turing degrees are indicated
  •  30
    Lattice initial segments of the hyperdegrees
    with Richard A. Shore
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (1): 103-130. 2010.
    We affirm a conjecture of Sacks [1972] by showing that every countable distributive lattice is isomorphic to an initial segment of the hyperdegrees, $\scr{D}_{h}$ . In fact, we prove that every sublattice of any hyperarithmetic lattice (and so, in particular, every countable, locally finite lattice) is isomorphic to an initial segment of $\scr{D}_{h}$ . Corollaries include the decidability of the two quantifier theory of $\scr{D}_{h}$ and the undecidability of its three quantifier theory. The ke…Read more
  •  27
    How much randomness is needed for statistics?
    with Antoine Taveneaux and Neil Thapen
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 165 (9): 1470-1483. 2014.
    In algorithmic randomness, when one wants to define a randomness notion with respect to some non-computable measure λ, a choice needs to be made. One approach is to allow randomness tests to access the measure λ as an oracle. The other approach is the opposite one, where the randomness tests are completely effective and do not have access to the information contained in λ. While the Hippocratic approach is in general much more restrictive, there are cases where the two coincide. The first author…Read more
  •  6
    Lowness for the class of Schnorr random sets
    with A. Nies and F. Stephan
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (3): 647-657. 2005.
    We answer a question of Ambos-Spies and Kuˇcera in the affirmative. They asked whether, when a real is low for Schnorr randomness, it is already low for Schnorr tests.
  •  44
    A strong law of computationally weak subsets
    Journal of Mathematical Logic 11 (1): 1-10. 2011.
    We show that in the setting of fair-coin measure on the power set of the natural numbers, each sufficiently random set has an infinite subset that computes no random set. That is, there is an almost sure event [Formula: see text] such that if [Formula: see text] then X has an infinite subset Y such that no element of [Formula: see text] is Turing computable from Y.
  •  470
    On a Conjecture of Dobrinen and Simpson concerning Almost Everywhere Domination
    with Stephen Binns, Manuel Lerman, and Reed Solomon
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1). 2006.
  •  29
    How much randomness is needed for statistics?
    with Antoine Taveneaux and Neil Thapen
    In S. Barry Cooper (ed.), Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, . pp. 395--404. 2012.
    In algorithmic randomness, when one wants to define a randomness notion with respect to some non-computable measure λ, a choice needs to be made. One approach is to allow randomness tests to access the measure λ as an oracle . The other approach is the opposite one, where the randomness tests are completely effective and do not have access to the information contained in λ . While the Hippocratic approach is in general much more restrictive, there are cases where the two coincide. The first auth…Read more
  •  41
    Comparing DNR and WWKL
    with Klaus Ambos-Spies, Steffen Lempp, and Theodore A. Slaman
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (4): 1089-1104. 2004.
    In Reverse Mathematics, the axiom system DNR, asserting the existence of diagonally non-recursive functions, is strictly weaker than WWKL0
  •  29
    The strength of the Grätzer-Schmidt theorem
    with Katie Brodhead, Mushfeq Khan, William A. Lampe, Paul Kim Long V. Nguyen, and Richard A. Shore
    Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (5-6): 687-704. 2016.
    The Grätzer-Schmidt theorem of lattice theory states that each algebraic lattice is isomorphic to the congruence lattice of an algebra. We study the reverse mathematics of this theorem. We also show thatthe set of indices of computable lattices that are complete is Π11\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$$\…Read more
  •  322
    Martin-Löf randomness and Galton–Watson processes
    with David Diamondstone
    Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (5): 519-529. 2012.
  •  36
    Self-Embeddings of Computable Trees
    with Stephen Binns, Manuel Lerman, James H. Schmerl, and Reed Solomon
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 49 (1): 1-37. 2008.
    We divide the class of infinite computable trees into three types. For the first and second types, 0' computes a nontrivial self-embedding while for the third type 0'' computes a nontrivial self-embedding. These results are optimal and we obtain partial results concerning the complexity of nontrivial self-embeddings of infinite computable trees considered up to isomorphism. We show that every infinite computable tree must have either an infinite computable chain or an infinite Π01 antichain. Thi…Read more
  •  14
    We show that Carmo and Jones’ condition 5 conflicts with the other conditions on their models for contrary-to-duty obligations. We then propose a resolution to the conflict.
  •  20
    Finding paths through narrow and wide trees
    with Stephen Binns
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (1): 349-360. 2009.
    We consider two axioms of second-order arithmetic. These axioms assert, in two different ways, that infinite but narrow binary trees always have infinite paths. We show that both axioms are strictly weaker than Weak König's Lemma, and incomparable in strength to the dual statement (WWKL) that wide binary trees have paths