Cathal O'Madagain

Universite Mohammed VI Polytechnique
  •  455
    Mind and Machine
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (2): 291-295. 2014.
    No abstract
  • The Origin of Pointing: Evidence for the Touch Hypothesis
    with O.' and Cathal Madagain
    Science Advances 5 (7). 2019.
  •  276
    The worst-motive fallacy: A negativity bias in motive attribution
    Psychological Science 31 (11): 1430--1438. 2020.
    In this article, we describe a hitherto undocumented fallacy-in the sense of a mistake in reasoning-constituted by a negativity bias in the way that people attribute motives to others. We call this the "worst-motive fallacy," and we conducted two experiments to investigate it. In Experiment 1, participants expected protagonists in a variety of fictional vignettes to pursue courses of action that satisfy the protagonists' worst motive, and furthermore, participants significantly expected the prot…Read more
  •  97
    This is a Paper about Demonstratives
    Philosophia 49 (2): 745-764. 2020.
    Demonstratives (words like ‘this’ and ‘that’) and indexicals (words like ‘I’, ‘here’, and ‘now’) seem intuitively to form a semantic family. Together they form the basic set of directly referring ‘context sensitive’ terms whose reference changes as the environment or identity of the speaker changes. Something that we might expect of a semantics for indexicals is therefore that it would be closely related to a semantics of demonstratives, although recent approaches have generally treated them sep…Read more
  •  87
    Concept Utility
    with Paul Egré
    Journal of Philosophy 116 (10): 525-554. 2019.
    Practices of concept-revision among scientists seem to indicate that concepts can be improved. In 2006, the International Astronomical Union revised the concept "Planet" so that it excluded Pluto, and insisting that the result was an improvement. But what could it mean for one concept or conceptual scheme to be better than another? Here we draw on the theory of epistemic utility to address this question. We show how the plausibility and informativeness of beliefs, two features that contribute to…Read more
  •  63
    Growing evidence indicates that our higher rational capacities depend on social interaction—that only through engaging with others do we acquire the ability to evaluate beliefs as true or false, or to reflect on and evaluate the reasons that support our beliefs. Up to now, however, we have had little understanding of how this works. Here we argue that a uniquely human socio-linguistic phenomenon which we call ‘joint attention to mental content’ plays a key role. JAM is the ability to focus toget…Read more
  •  854
    Group Agents: Persons, Mobs, or Zombies?
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 20 (2): 271-287. 2012.
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies, Volume 20, Issue 2, Page 271-287, May 2012
  •  400
    Outsourcing Concepts: Deference, the Extended Mind, and Expanding our Epistemic Capacity
    In J. Adam Carter, Andy Clark, Jesper Kallestrup, Orestis Palermos & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Socially Extended Knowledge, Oxford University Press. 2018.
    Semantic deference is the apparent phenomenon whereby some of our concepts have their content fixed by the minds of others. The phenomenon is puzzling both in terms of how such concepts are supposed to work, but also in terms of why we should have concepts whose content is fixed by others. Here I argue that if we rethink semantic deference in terms of extended mind reasoning we find answers to both of these questions: the minds of others can be understood to play a role in storing the semantic k…Read more
  •  21
    Intentionality
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2014.
    Intentionality If I think about a piano, something in my thought picks out a piano. If I talk about cigars, something in my speech refers to cigars. This feature of thoughts and words, whereby they pick out, refer to, or are about things, is intentionality. In a word, intentionality is aboutness. Many mental states exhibit […].
  •  247
    Davidson and Husserl both arrived independently at a startling conclusion: that we need to interact with others in order to acquire the concept of objectivity, or to realize that the world we are in exists independently of us. Here I discuss both of their arguments, and argue that there are problems with each. However, I then I argue that each thinker provided us with one key insight that can be combined to provide a more compelling argument for the claim. Finally I discuss some recent work in d…Read more
  •  820
    Can groups have concepts? Semantics for collective intentions
    Philosophical Issues 24 (1): 347-363. 2014.
    A substantial literature supports the attribution of intentional states such as beliefs and desires to groups. But within this literature, there is no substantial account of group concepts. Since on many views, one cannot have an intentional state without having concepts, such a gap undermines the cogency of accounts of group intentionality. In this paper I aim to provide an account of group concepts. First I argue that to fix the semantics of the sentences groups use to make their decisions or …Read more
  •  613
    To avoid difficulties facing intention-based accounts of indexicals, Cohen () recently defends a conventionalist account that focuses on the context of tokening. On this view, a token of ‘here’ or ‘now’ refers to the place or time at which it tokens. However, although promising, such an account faces a serious problem: in many speech acts, multiple apparent tokens are produced. If I call Alaska from Paris and say ‘I'm here now’, an apparent token of my utterance will be produced in both Paris an…Read more