•  4
    Prior's Theory of Propositions
    Analysis 37 (3): 104-112. 1977.
  •  53
    Mathematical Relativism
    with Hugly Philip and Sayward Charles
    History and Philosophy of Logic 10 (1): 53-65. 1989.
    We set out a doctrine about truth for the statements of mathematics?a doctrine which we think is a worthy competitor to realist views in the philosophy of mathematics?and argue that this doctrine, which we shall call ?mathematical relativism?, withstands objections better than do other non-realist accounts
  • Chapter 9: Thesis Two
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 241-253. 2006.
  •  425
    Strawson on Categories
    Journal of Critical Analysis 7 (3): 83-88. 1978.
    A type theory constructed with reference to a particular language will associate with each monadic predicate P of that language a class of individuals C(P) of which it is categorically significant to predicate P (or which P spans, for short). The extension of P is a subset of C(P), which is a subset of the language’s universe of discourse. The set C(P) is a category discriminated by the language. The relation 'is spanned by the same predicates as' divides the language’s universe of discourse int…Read more
  •  168
    Whereas arithmetical quantification is substitutional in the sense that a some-quantification is true only if some instance of it is true, it does not follow (and, in fact, is not true) that an account of the truth-conditions of the sentences of the language of arithmetic can be given by a substitutional semantics. A substitutional semantics fails in a most fundamental fashion: it fails to articulate the truth-conditions of the quantifications with which it is concerned. This is what is defended…Read more
  •  323
    A Wittgensteinian Philosophy of Mathematics
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 15 (2): 55-69. 2005.
    Three theses are gleaned from Wittgenstein’s writing. First, extra-mathematical uses of mathematical expressions are not referential uses. Second, the senses of the expressions of pure mathematics are to be found in their uses outside of mathematics. Third, mathematical truth is fixed by mathematical proof. These theses are defended. The philosophy of mathematics defined by the three theses is compared with realism, nominalism, and formalism.
  • Chapter 5: Existence, Number, and Realism
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 129-155. 2006.
  •  238
    Propositions and eternal sentences
    Mind 77 (308): 537-542. 1968.
    Two different uses of ‘proposition’ are distinguished: the meaning of an eternal sentence is distinguished from that which can be asserted, believed, conjectured, and so on. It is argued that, in the second sense of ‘proposition’, it is not the case that every proposition can be expressed by an eternal sentence.
  • References
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 285-287. 2006.
  •  51
    Absurdity and spanning
    with Stephen H. Voss
    Philosophia 2 (3): 227-238. 1972.
    On the basis of observations J. J. C. Smart once made concerning the absurdity of sentences like 'The seat of the bed is hard', a plausible case can be made that there is little point to developing a theory of types, particularly one of the sort envisaged by Fred Sommers. The authors defend such theories against this objection by a partial elucidation of the distinctions between the concepts of spanning and predicability and between category mistakenness and absurdity in general. The argument su…Read more
  •  64
    More on Propositional Identity
    Analysis 39 (3): 129-132. 1979.
    We give a semantical account of propositional identity which is stronger than mutual entailment. That is, according to our account: (1) if A = B is true in a model, so are A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A. (2) There exist models m such that A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A are true in m but A = B is not true in m. According to our account the following rule is sound: (3) from (.. A..) = (.. B..) infer A = B. The paper respondes to a criticism of an earlier paper by James Freeman
  •  10
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1): 151-173. 1991.
  •  125
    W.d. Ross on acting from motives
    Journal of Value Inquiry 22 (4): 299-306. 1988.
    This paper defends a position held by W, D, Ross that it is no part of one’s duty to have a certain motive since one cannot by choice have it here and now.
  •  80
    Indenumerability and substitutional quantification
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (4): 358-366. 1982.
    We here establish two theorems which refute a pair of what we believe to be plausible assumptions about differences between objectual and substitutional quantification. The assumptions (roughly stated) are as follows: (1) there is at least one set d and denumerable first order language L such that d is the domain set of no interpretation of L in which objectual and substitutional quantification coincide. (2) There exist interpreted, denumerable, first order languages K with indenumerable domains…Read more
  •  504
    Are All Tautologies True?
    Logique Et Analyse 125 (125-126): 3-14. 1989.
    The paper asks: are all tautologies true in a language with truth-value gaps? It answers that they are not. No tautology is false, of course, but not all are true. It also contends that not all contradictions are false in a language with truth-value gaps, though none are true.
  •  43
    God and empty terms
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 18 (3). 1985.
    This paper is a criticism of Plantinga’s analysis of a version of the ontological argument. He thinks it is obvious that his version is valid and that the only question of interest is whether a key premise is true. The paper lays out two relevant semantical accounts of modal logic. It contends that Plantinga needs to show that one is preferable to the other.
  •  56
    More on propositional identity
    Analysis 39 (3): 129-132. 1979.
    We give a semantical account of propositional identity which is stronger than mutual entailment. That is, according to our account: (1) if A = B is true in a model, so are A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A. (2) There exist models m such that A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A are true in m but A = B is not true in m. According to our account the following rule is sound: (3) from (.. A..) = (.. B..) infer A = B. The paper is a response to a paper by James Freeman to an earlier paper by us.
  •  31
    A semantical account of the vicious circle principle
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (3): 595-598. 1979.
    Here we give a semantical account of propositional quantification that is intended to formally represent Russell’s view that one cannot express a proposition about "all" propositions. According to the account the authors give, Russell’s view bears an interesting relation to the view that there are no sets which are members of themselves.
  •  28
    Is English infinite?
    Philosophical Papers 17 (2): 141-151. 1988.
    It is argued that English is finite. By this is meant that it contains only finitely many expressions. The conclusion is reached by arguing: (1) only finitely many expressions of English are tokenable; (2) if E is an expression of English, then E is tokenable.
  •  21
    Convention T and Basic Law V
    Analysis 62 (4): 289-292. 2002.
  •  102
    Did the greeks discover the irrationals?
    Philosophy 74 (2): 169-176. 1999.
    A popular view is that the great discovery of Pythagoras was that there are irrational numbers, e.g., the positive square root of two. Against this it is argued that mathematics and geometry, together with their applications, do not show that there are irrational numbers or compel assent to that proposition.
  •  124
    Mark Steiner criticizes some remarks Wittgenstein makes about Gödel. Steiner takes Wittgenstein to be disputing a mathematical result. The paper argues that Wittgenstein does no such thing. The contrast between the realist and the demonstrativist concerning mathematical truth is examined. Wittgenstein is held to side with neither camp. Rather, his point is that a realist argument is inconclusive
  •  94
    The Lessons of the Liar
    Theory and Decision 11 (1): 55-70. 1979.
    The paper argues that the liar paradox teaches us these lessons about English. First, the paradox-yielding sentence is a sentence of English that is neither true nor false in English. Second, there is no English name for any such thing as a set of all and only true sentences of English. Third, ‘is true in English’ does not satisfy the axiom of comprehension.
  • Chapter 10: Thesis Three
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 254-283. 2006.
  •  20
    Remarks on Peano Arithmetic
    Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 20 (1): 27-32. 2000.
    Russell held that the theory of natural numbers could be derived from three primitive concepts: number, successor and zero. This leaves out multiplication and addition. Russell introduces these concepts by recursive definition. It is argued that this does not render addition or multiplication any less primitive than the other three. To this it might be replied that any recursive definition can be transformed into a complete or explicit definition with the help of a little set theory. But that is…Read more
  •  163
    Tarski and Proper Classes
    Analysis 40 (4): 6-11. 1980.
    In this paper the authors argue that if Tarski’s definition of truth for the calculus of classes is correct, then set theories which assert the existence of proper classes (classes which are not the member of anything) are incorrect.
  •  410
    Bound Variables and Schematic Letters
    Logique Et Analyse 95 (95): 425-429. 1981.
    The paper purports to show, against Quine, that one can construct a language , which results from the extension of the theory of truth functions by introducing sentence letter quantification. Next a semantics is provided for this language. It is argued that the quantification is neither substitutional nor requires one to consider the sentence letters as taking entities as values.
  •  10
    Notes and Discussions
    Dialectica 57 (3): 315-322. 2003.
    This paper seeks to explain why the argument from analogy seems strong to an analogist such as Mill and weak to the skeptic. The inference from observed behavior to the existence of feelings, sensations, etc., in other subjects is justified, but its justification depends on taking observed behavior and feelings, sensations, and so on, to be not merely correlated, but connected. It is claimed that this is what Mill had in mind