•  6
    Reason and Commitment
    Philosophical Quarterly 24 (97): 375-378. 1974.
  •  2
    The Autonomy of Relations
    Facta Philosophica 6 (1): 3-43. 2004.
  •  17
    The Power of Logic
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (1): 79-81. 2001.
  •  59
    My thesis is that there are good reasons for a philosophical account of measurement to deal primarily with the properties or magnitudes of objects measured, rather than with the objects themselves. The account I present here embodies both a realism about measurement and a realism about the existence of the properties involved in measurement. It thus provides an alternative to most current treatments of measurement, many of which are operationalistic or conventionalistic, and nearly all of which …Read more
  •  16
    Intensional Logic and the Metaphysics of Intentionality (review)
    Noûs 27 (2): 243. 1993.
  •  2
    Essays on the Philosophy of W. V. Quine (edited book)
    with Robert W. Shahan and W. V. Quine
    University of Oklahoma Press, C1979. 1979.
  •  48
    Belief and predication
    Noûs 17 (2): 197-220. 1983.
  •  53
    Causation and Identity
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1): 593-622. 1984.
  •  68
    Many linguists, including Noam Chomsky, contend that language in the sense we ordinary think of it, in the sense that people in Germany speak German, is a historical or social or political notion, rather than a scientific one. For example, German and Dutch are much closer to one another than various dialects of Chinese are. But the rough, commonsense divisions between languages will suffice for our purposes.
  •  90
    Leibnizian expression
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (1): 65-99. 1995.
  •  12
    Editor’s Note
    Southwestern Journal of Philosophy 9 (2): 5-6. 1978.
  •  6
    REVIEWS-The power of logic
    with C. Stephen Layman
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (2): 218-219. 2004.
  •  16
    The Power of Logic
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (2): 218-219. 2004.
  •  45
    Sense and Nonsense
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 9 (4). 1979.
    “What kind of psychological theory could relate our use of words to sets of possible worlds?” So queries a recent author, but the question is rhetorical, the insinuation being that any analysis or explanation of semantical notions in terms of possible worlds will involve an account that won't square with a naturalistic view of language acquisition or use. Such feelings are widespread; my purpose here is to argue that they are unjustified.
  •  56
    Kantian Derivations
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (3). 1983.
    Although Kant's attempts in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals to derive statements of specific duties from the categorical imperative have received much attention, there is still disagreement over the strategies of particular derivations, the status of the auxiliary assumptions employed therein, and the principles at work in the derivations generally. Yet an understanding of these matters is indispensable for a proper understanding of the Groundwork and bears on a much wider class of e…Read more
  •  133
    Complex predicates and logics for properties and relations
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (3): 295-325. 1998.
    In this paper I present a formal language in which complex predicates stand for properties and relations, and assignments of denotations to complex predicates and assignments of extensions to the properties and relations they denote are both homomorphisms. This system affords a fresh perspective on several important philosophical topics, highlighting the algebraic features of properties and clarifying the sense in which properties can be represented by their extensions. It also suggests a natura…Read more
  •  17
    C.I.Lewis’s calculus of predicates
    History and Philosophy of Logic 16 (1): 19-37. 1995.
    In 1951 C.I.Lewis published a logic of general terms that he called the calculus of predicates. Although this system is of less significance than Lewis’s earlier work on proposition...
  •  486
    » The Nature of Natural Laws «
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (3): 1982. 1982.
    That laws of nature play a vital role in explanation, prediction, and inductive inference is far clearer than the nature of the laws themselves. My hope here is to shed some light on the nature of natural laws by developing and defending the view that they involve genuine relations between properties. Such a position is suggested by Plato, and more recent versions have been sketched by several writers.~ But I am not happy with any of these accounts, not so much because they lack detail or engend…Read more
  •  58
    Relativism and representation
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (1): 151-155. 1988.
  •  5
    Abstract entities
    In Theodore Sider, John Hawthorne & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, Blackwell. 2008.
  •  311
    It is argued that a number of important, and seemingly disparate, types of representation are species of a single relation, here called structural representation, that can be described in detail and studied in a way that is of considerable philosophical interest. A structural representation depends on the existence of a common structure between a representation and that which it represents, and it is important because it allows us to reason directly about the representation in order to draw conc…Read more
  •  17
    Review (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (4): 603-609. 1995.
  •  50
    Logic and the Empirical Conception of Properties
    Philosophical Topics 21 (2): 199-231. 1993.
  •  56
    Complex predicates and conversion principles
    Philosophical Studies 87 (1): 1-32. 1997.
  •  1