•  97
    Christine M. Korsgaard presents a compelling new view of our moral relationships to the other animals. She offers challenging answers to such questions as: Are people superior to animals, and does it matter morally if we are? Is it all right for us to eat animals, experiment on them, make them work for us, and keep them as pets?
  •  30
    Species-Being and the Badness of Extinction and Death
    Zeitschrift Für Ethik Und Moralphilosophie 1 (1): 143-162. 2018.
    This paper offers an account of the property Feuerbach and Marx called “species-being,” the human being’s distinctive tendency to identify herself as a member of her species, and to think of the species as a “we.” It links the notion to Kant’s theory of rights, arguing that every claim of right commits the maker of that claim to something like world government, and therefore to the conception of humanity as a collective agent. It also links species-being to the concept of practical identity, arg…Read more
  •  11
    Autoconstitución en la ética de Platón y Kant
    with Javier Fuentes González and Eva Monardes Pereira
    Revista Ethika+ 6 193-224. 2022.
    Platón y Kant plantean un modelo “constitucional” del alma, en el que la razón y el apetito o la pasión tienen diferentes roles estructurales y funcionales en la generación de la motivación, en contraposición al común “modelo combativo,” en el que son mostrados como fuentes de motivación independientes que luchan por el control. Desde el punto de vista del modelo constitucional, podemos explicar qué hace que una acción sea diferente de un evento. Lo que hace que una acción sea atribuible a una p…Read more
  •  31
    Valuing animals, nature, and our own animal nature: A reply to Maclean, Schapiro, and Wallace
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 105 (1): 242-257. 2022.
  •  22
    Précis of fellow creatures: Our obligations to the other animals
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 105 (1): 216-219. 2022.
  •  348
    If I understand him correctly, Derek Parfit’s views place us, philosophically speaking, in a very small box. According to Parfit, normativity is an irreducible non-natural property that is independent of the human mind. That is to say, there are normative truths - truths about what we ought to do and to want, or about reasons for doing and wanting things. The truths in question are synthetic a priori truths, and accessible to us only by some sort of rational intuition. Parfit supposes that if we…Read more
  •  2
  •  13
    Agindo por uma razão
    Dissertatio 34 35-62. 2011.
    Neste ensaio a autora intenta discutir o que uma razão prática é, isto é, a que nos estamos referindo quando falamos sobre a razão para uma ação, bem como sobre o que ocorre quando alguém age por uma razão. Nesse sentido, ela evoca especialmente Aristóteles e Kant com o propósito de dar uma resposta a essa questão. Essa estratégia distinguirá sua resposta da resposta dada por filósofos contemporâneos. Assim, ela irá conectar sua descrição do que sejam razões com um aspecto da Razão tal como esta…Read more
  •  18
    Ignatieff, M. 107
    with V. Jabri, I. Kant, J. Keane, M. Keck, C. Lopez-Guerra, M. Loughlin, and T. McCarthy
    In Eva Erman & Ludvig Beckman (eds.), Territories of Citizenship, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 170. 2012.
  •  7
    The Categorical Imperative
    Kant Studien 77 183-202. 1986.
  •  5
    The Sources of Normativity
    Philosophical Quarterly 49 (196): 384-394. 1999.
  •  182
    Constitutivism and the virtues
    Philosophical Explorations 22 (2): 98-116. 2019.
    In Self-Constitution, I argue that the principles governing action are “constitutive standards” of agency, standards that arise from the nature of agency itself. To be an agent is to be autonomousl...
  •  93
    Fellow Creatures. Our Obligations to the Other Animals
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 73 (1): 165-168. 2018.
  •  375
    Personhood, animals, and the law
    Think 12 (34): 25-32. 2013.
    ExtractThe idea that all the entities in the world may be, for legal and moral purposes, divided into the two categories of ‘persons’ and ‘things’ comes down to us from the tradition of Roman law. In the law, a ‘person’ is essentially the subject of rights and obligations, while a thing may be owned as property. In ethics, a person is an object of respect, to be valued for her own sake, and never to be used as a mere means to an end, while a thing has only a derivative value, and may be used as …Read more
  •  70
    Animals: Ethics, Agency, Culture
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 25 1-5. 2018.
  •  548
    The Claims of Animals and the Needs of Strangers: Two Cases of Imperfect Right
    Journal of Practical Ethics 6 (1): 19-51. 2018.
    This paper argues for a conception of the natural rights of non-human animals grounded in Kant’s explanation of the foundation of human rights. The rights in question are rights that are in the first instance held against humanity collectively speaking—against our species conceived as an organized body capable of collective action. The argument proceeds by first developing a similar case for the right of every human individual who is in need of aid to get it, and then showing why the situation o…Read more
  •  102
    I—Prospects for a Naturalistic Explanation of the Good
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 92 (1): 111-131. 2018.
    In this paper I explore the possibility of explaining why there is such a thing as the good in naturalistic terms. More specifically, I seek an explanation of the fact that some things are good-for human beings and the other animals in the final sense of good: worth aiming at. I trace the existence of the final good to the existence of conscious agents. I propose that the final good for an animal is her own well-functioning as the kind of creature she is, taken as an end of action, and that havi…Read more
  •  113
    Reclaiming the History of Ethics: Essays for John Rawls (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1997.
    The essays in this volume offer an approach to the history of moral and political philosophy that takes its inspiration from John Rawls. All the contributors are philosophers who have studied with Rawls and they offer this collection in his honour. The distinctive feature of this approach is to address substantive normative questions in moral and political philosophy through an analysis of the texts and theories of major figures in the history of the subject: Aristotle, Hobbes, Hume, Rousseau, K…Read more
  •  22
    Valorar nuestra humanidad
    Signos Filosóficos 13 (26): 13-41. 2011.
    En este artículo discuto las diferentes actitudes implícitas en "valorar" nuestra humanidad, según lo entiende Kant. El atributo distintivo de la humanidad es la capacidad de la elección moral racional. Según mi argumento, valorar nuestra capacidad moral nos compromete con el bien moral, lo cual no ..
  •  25
    The Practice of Value
    Mind 114 (453): 189-192. 2005.
  •  768
    The sources of normativity
    Cambridge University Press. 1996.
    Ethical concepts are, or purport to be, normative. They make claims on us: they command, oblige, recommend, or guide. Or at least when we invoke them, we make claims on one another; but where does their authority over us - or ours over one another - come from? Christine Korsgaard identifies four accounts of the source of normativity that have been advocated by modern moral philosophers: voluntarism, realism, reflective endorsement, and the appeal to autonomy. She traces their history, showing ho…Read more
  •  690
    To later generations, much of the moral philosophy of the twentieth century will look like a struggle to escape from utilitarianism. We seem to succeed in disproving one utilitarian doctrine, only to find ourselves caught in the grip of another. I believe that this is because a basic feature of the consequentialist outlook still pervades and distorts our thinking: the view that the business of morality is to bring something about . Too often, the rest of us have pitched our protests as if we wer…Read more
  •  1366
    The right to lie: Kant on dealing with evil
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 15 (4): 325-349. 1986.
    One of the great difficulties with Kant’s moral philosophy is that it seems to imply that our moral obligations leave us powerless in the face of evil. Kant’s theory sets a high ideal of conduct and tells us to live up to that ideal regardless of what other persons are doing. The results may be very bad. But Kant says that the law "remains in full force, because it commands categorically" (G, 438-39/57).* The most weI1—known example of...
  •  429
    The Normativity of Instrumental Reason
    In Garrett Cullity & Berys Gaut (eds.), Ethics and Practical Reason, Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1997.
    This paper criticizes two accounts of the normativity of practical principles: the empiricist account and the rationalist or realist account. It argues against the empiricist view, focusing on the Humean texts that are usually taken to be its locus classicus. It then argues both against the dogmatic rationalist view, and for the Kantian view, through a discussion of Kant's own remarks about instrumental rationality in the second section of the Groundwork. It further argues that the instrumental …Read more
  •  119
    The Myth of Egoism
    In Peter Baumann & Monika Betzler (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays, Cambridge University Press. pp. 57. 1999.
    This is the text of The Lindley Lecture for 1999, given by Christine Korsgaard, an American philosopher