-
3“We May Stand Aloof”: Mill’s Natural PenaltiesJournal of the History of Philosophy 60 (3): 453-473. 2022.ARRAY
-
11One meat-eater’s modus ponens...: A response to NorcrossSouthwest Philosophy Review 20 (2): 175-177. 2004.
-
28Moral Education and Rule ConsequentialismPhilosophical Quarterly 71 (1): 120-140. 2021.Rule consequentialism holds that an action's moral standing depends on its relation to the moral code whose general adoption would have the best consequences. Heretofore rule consequentialists have understood the notion of a code's being generally adopted in terms of its being generally obeyed or, more commonly, its being generally accepted. I argue that these ways of understanding general adoption lead to unacceptable formulations of the theory. For instance, Brad Hooker, Michael Ridge, and Hol…Read more
-
10The Place of “The Liberty of Thought and Discussion” in On LibertyUtilitas 33 (2): 133-149. 2021.I consider whether Mill intends for us to see the arguments that constitute his defense of the “Liberty of Thought and Discussion” in chapter 2 ofOn Libertyas a part of his larger case for the “harm” or “liberty” principle (LP). Several commentators depict this chapter as a digression that interrupts the flow between his introduction of this principle in the first chapter and his exposition and defense of it in the final three. I will argue instead for a reading ofOn Libertyon which chapter 2 is…Read more
-
IntroductionIn Ben Eggleston, Dale E. Miller & David Weinstein (eds.), John Stuart Mill and the Art of Life. pp. 3-18. 2011.
-
20Compunction, Second-Personal Morality, and Moral ReasonsEthical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (3): 719-733. 2018.In The Second-Person Standpoint and subsequent essays, Stephen Darwall develops an account of morality that is “second-personal” in virtue of holding that what we are morally obligated to do is what others can legitimately demand that we do, i.e., what they can hold us accountable for doing through moral reactive attitudes like blame. Similarly, what it would be wrong for us to do is what others can legitimately demand that we abstain from doing. As part of this account, Darwall argues for the p…Read more
-
21"Freedom and Resentment" and ConsequentialismJournal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 8 (2): 1-23. 2014.In The Second-Person Standpoint, Stephen Darwall offers an interpretation of P. F. Strawson’s “Freedom and Resentment” according to which the essay advances the thesis that good consequences are the “wrong kind of reason” to justify “practices of punishment and moral responsibility.” Darwall names this thesis “Strawson’s Point.” I argue for a different reading of Strawson, one according to which he holds this thesis only in a qualified way and, more generally, is not the unequivocal critic of co…Read more
-
Reluctant Florists, Same-Sex Weddings, and Mill’s Doctrine of LibertyPublic Affairs Quarterly 30 (4): 287-311. 2016.
-
35One meat-eater’s modus ponens...: A response to NorcrossSouthwest Philosophy Review 20 (2): 175-177. 2004.
-
9A Companion to Mill (edited book)John Wiley & Sons, Inc.. 2016.This Companion offers a state-of-the-art survey of the work of John Stuart Mill – one which covers the historical influences on Mill, his theoretical, moral and social philosophy, as well as his relation to contemporary movements. Its contributors include both senior scholars with established expertise in Mill’s thought and new emerging interpreters. Each essay acts as a ‘go-to’ resource for those seeking to understand an aspect of Mill’s thought or to familiarise themselves with the contours of…Read more
-
34John Stuart Mill's Civic LiberalismHistory of Political Thought 21 (1): 88-113. 2000.Although it is frequently overlooked, J.S. Mill's political philosophy has a significant civic component; he is a committed believer in the value of active and disinterested participation in public affairs by the citizens of liberal democracies, and he advocates a programme of civic education intended to cultivate public spirit. In the first half of this essay I present a brief but systematic exploration of his thought's civic dimension. In the second half I defend Mill's civic liberalism agains…Read more
-
29J. S. Mill: Moral, Social and Political ThoughtPolity. 2010.This book offers a clear and highly readable introduction to the ethical and social-political philosophy of John Stuart Mill. Dale E. Miller argues for a "utopian" reading of Mill's utilitarianism. He analyses Mill's views on happiness and goes on to show the practical, social and political implications that can be drawn from his utilitarianism, especially in relation to the construction of morality, individual freedom, democratic reform, and economic organization. By highlighting the utopian th…Read more
-
Public Spirit and Liberal Democracy: John Stuart Mill's Civic LiberalismDissertation, University of Pittsburgh. 1999.The civic republican tradition in political thought includes Niccolo Machiavelli, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, and Alexis de Tocqueville. The belief that it is imperative that citizens participate actively and disinterestedly in public affairs, i.e., that they possess "civic virtue" or "public spirit" is a prominent family resemblance between its members. Civic republican thought has undergone a recent resurgence, and one consequence is that political philosophers and other theorists have begun to ask…Read more
-
51Georgios Varouxakis, mill on nationality (london: Routledge, 2002), pp. IX + 169Utilitas 16 (2): 231-233. 2004.
-
164The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism (edited book)Cambridge University Press. 2014.Utilitarianism, the approach to ethics based on the maximization of overall well-being, continues to have great traction in moral philosophy and political thought. This Companion offers a systematic exploration of its history, themes, and applications. First, it traces the origins and development of utilitarianism via the work of Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill, Henry Sidgwick, and others. The volume then explores issues in the formulation of utilitarianism, including act versus rule utilitaria…Read more
-
69Utilitarianism and the Headache That Just Won't Go Away: Reply to CainSouthwest Philosophy Review 22 (2): 147-149. 2006.
-
71Mill, rule utilitarianism, and the incoherence objectionIn Ben Eggleston, Dale E. Miller & D. Weinstein (eds.), John Stuart Mill and the Art of Life, Oxford University Press. pp. 94. 2011.
-
40Jonathan Haidt, The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion , pp. xvii + 419 (review)Utilitas 26 (1): 124-127. 2014.
-
67Reactive Attitudes and the Hare–Williams Debate: Towards a New Consequentialist Moral PsychologyPhilosophical Quarterly 64 (254): 39-59. 2014.Bernard Williams charges that the moral psychology built into R. M. Hare’s utilitarianism is incoherent in virtue of demanding a bifurcated kind of moral thinking that is possible only for agents who fail to reflect properly on their own practical decision making. I mount a qualified defence of Hare’s view by drawing on the account of the ‘reactive attitudes’ found in P. F. Strawson’s ‘Freedom and Resentment’. Against Williams, I argue that the ‘resilience’ of the reactive attitudes ensures that…Read more
-
11Mill’s Conception of Pleasure: Meeting West in the MiddleSouthwest Philosophy Review 31 (1): 157-166. 2015.
-
166Hooker on Rule-Consequentialism and VirtueUtilitas 25 (3): 421-432. 2013.In Ideal Code, Real World, Brad Hooker proposes an account of the relation between his rule-consequentialism and virtue according to which the virtues (1) have intrinsic value and (2) are identical with the dispositions that are of the ideal code. While it is not clear whether Hooker actually intends to endorse this account or only intends to moot it for discussion, I argue that for him to adopt it would be a mistake. Not only would this mean that his moral theory was no longer properly a conseq…Read more
Norfolk, Virginia, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Normative Ethics |
Social and Political Philosophy |
19th Century Philosophy |
Areas of Interest
Applied Ethics |
Meta-Ethics |
Philosophy of Law |