• Adjectival modification and gradation
    In Shalom Lappin & Chris Fox (eds.), Handbook of Contemporary Semantic Theory, Wiley-blackwell. 2015.
  •  27
    Decomposing relevance in conditionals
    Mind and Language 38 (3): 644-668. 2023.
    Conditionals frequently convey that the antecedent is relevant to the consequent. Recently many authors have argued that this relevance is part of the conventional meaning of conditionals, but this approach fails to account for many examples where a conditional is used to conveyirrelevance of antecedent to consequent. Both types of conditionals are best explained by a conventional meaning with no relevance requirement, and a separate process of coherence establishment among successive clauses in…Read more
  •  23
    Nested conditionals and genericity in the de Finetti semantics
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 10 (1): 42-52. 2021.
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, Volume 10, Issue 1, Page 42-52, March 2021.
  •  23
    What we can learn from how trivalent conditionals avoid triviality
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 63 (9-10): 1087-1114. 2020.
    ABSTRACT A trivalent theory of indicative conditionals automatically enforces Stalnaker's thesis – the equation between probabilities of conditionals and conditional probabilities. This result holds because the trivalent semantics requires, for principled reasons, a modification of the ratio definition of conditional probability in order to accommodate the possibility of undefinedness. I explain how this modification is motivated and how it allows the trivalent semantics to avoid a number of wel…Read more
  •  48
    The basic Bayesian model of credence states, where each individual’s belief state is represented by a single probability measure, has been criticized as psychologically implausible, unable to represent the intuitive distinction between precise and imprecise probabilities, and normatively unjustifiable due to a need to adopt arbitrary, unmotivated priors. These arguments are often used to motivate a model on which imprecise credal states are represented by sets of probability measures. I connect …Read more
  •  5
    The European Summer School in Logic, Language and Information is organized every year by the Association for Logic, Language and Information in different sites around Europe. The main focus of ESSLLI is on the interface between linguistics, logic and computation. ESSLLI offers foundational, introductory and advanced courses, as well as workshops, covering a wide variety of topics within the three areas of interest: Language and Computation, Language and Logic, and Logic and Computation. During t…Read more
  •  38
    Modality, Scale Structure, and Scalar Reasoning
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 95 (4): 461-490. 2014.
    Epistemic and deontic comparatives differ in how they interact with disjunction. I argue that this difference provides a compelling empirical argument against the semantics of Kratzer, which predicts that all modal comparatives should interact with disjunction in the same way. Interestingly, an identical distinction is found in the semantics of non-modal adjectives: additive adjectives like ‘heavy’ behave logically like epistemic comparatives, and intermediate adjectives like ‘hot’ behave like d…Read more
  •  121
    Adjectival vagueness in a Bayesian model of interpretation
    with Noah D. Goodman
    Synthese 194 (10): 3801-3836. 2017.
    We derive a probabilistic account of the vagueness and context-sensitivity of scalar adjectives from a Bayesian approach to communication and interpretation. We describe an iterated-reasoning architecture for pragmatic interpretation and illustrate it with a simple scalar implicature example. We then show how to enrich the apparatus to handle pragmatic reasoning about the values of free variables, explore its predictions about the interpretation of scalar adjectives, and show how this model impl…Read more
  •  129
    Abstract:   Chomsky (1986) has claimed that the prima facie incompatibility between descriptive linguistics and semantic externalism proves that an externalist semantics is impossible. Although it is true that a strong form of externalism does not cohere with descriptive linguistics, sociolinguistic theory can unify the two approaches. The resulting two-level theory reconciles descriptivism, mentalism, and externalism by construing community languages as a function of social identification. This…Read more
  •  34
    How many kinds of reasoning? Inference, probability, and natural language semantics
    with Noah D. Goodman
    Cognition 136 (C): 123-134. 2015.
  •  60
    Semantic Normativity and Coordination Games: Social Externalism Deflated
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 10 (3): 209-228. 2010.
    Individualists and externalists about language take themselves to be disagreeing about the basic subject matter of the study of language. Are linguistic facts are really facts about individuals, or really facts about language use in a community?The right answer to this question, I argue, is ‘Yes’. Both individualistic and social facts are crucial to a complete understanding of human language. The relationship between the theories inspired by these facts is analogous to the relationship between a…Read more
  •  61
    Must, knowledge, and (in)directness
    Natural Language Semantics 24 (2): 117-163. 2016.
    This paper presents corpus and experimental data that problematize the traditional analysis of must as a strong necessity modal, as recently revived and defended by von Fintel and Gillies :351–383, 2010). I provide naturalistic examples showing that must p can be used alongside an explicit denial of knowledge of p or certainty in p, and that it can be conjoined with an expression indicating that p is not certain or that not-p is possible. I also report the results of an experiment involving lott…Read more