•  2
    Qu’est-ce qui est non-conceptuel, l’etat ou son contenu?
    Facta Philosophica 6 (1): 77-95. 2004.
  •  1
    Quatorze observations topographiques sur les contenus et les normes
    Facta Philosophica 4 (2): 177-199. 2002.
  •  12
    Making „Reasons " Explicit. How Normative is Brandom's Inferentialism?
    Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 13 (1): 127-145. 2008.
    This paper asks whether Brandom has provided a sufficiently clear account of the basic normative concepts of commitment and entitlement, on which his normative inferentialism seems to rest, and of how they contribute to explain the inferential articulation of conceptual contents. I show that Brandom's claim that these concepts are analogous to the concepts of obligation and permission cannot be right, and argue that the normative character of the concept of commitment is dubious. This leads me t…Read more
  • Reasons and Supervenience
    In Bartosz Brożek, Antonino Rotolo & Jerzy Stelmach (eds.), Supervenience and Normativity, Springer. 2017.
  • Essais sur l'intentionnalité et le langage (edited book)
    Vrin-Bellarmin. 1992.
  •  6
    Mind, Davidson and Reality
    Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 9 (1-2). 2005.
    The aim of this article is to show that the prospects for intentional irreal-ism are much brighter than it is generally thought. In the first section, I provide a general characterization of some of the various forms that the realism/irrealism debates might take. In the second, I ask whether there is any defensible form of realism about intentional states. I show that most candidates are nearly trivially false, and that the only form of in-tentional realism which is not, is a restricted one whic…Read more
  •  10
    Que Sera Sera
    Dialectica 54 (4): 247-264. 2000.
    Having suggested that a salient feature of philosophical naturalism is to deny that there are non‐natural norms, I make a distinction between a moderate naturalism, which admits the existence of natural norms, and a radical naturalism which denies it. On the assumption that intentional facts are irreducibly normative, their existence would thus seem to raise a problem for moderate epistemological naturalism. I argue that no non‐trivial naturalistic explanation of conceptual intentionality is to …Read more
  •  10
    Between Phenomenalism and Objectivism
    Journal of Philosophical Research 30 189-214. 2005.
    Brandom (1994) claims to have succeeded in showing how certain kinds of social practices can institute objective deontic statuses and confer objective conceptual contents on certain performances. This paper proposes a reconstruction of how, on Brandom’s views, this is supposed to come about, and a critical examination of the explicit arguments offered in support for this claim.
  •  26
    Sommes-nous tous des épiphénomènes ?
    Philosophiques 35 (1): 119-125. 2008.
  •  24
    Le programme de Davidson et les langues naturelles
    Dialogue 24 (2): 195-212. 1985.
    Une théorie davidsonienne de la signification pour une langue L prend la forme d'une theorie tarskienne de la véeritée-dans-L. Une telle théeorie sera absolument radicale s'il est possible d'éetablir qu'elle est tarskienne, c'est-à-dire conforme à la convention T de Tarski, en n'utilisant que des donnéees empiriques dont la description ne fait intervenir aucun concept linguistique, tandis qu'elle sera relativement radicale s'il est possible d'éetablir qu'elle est tarskienne en n'utilisant que de…Read more
  •  17
    Rationality and Intentionality
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 43 (1): 125-141. 1992.
    The view that in radical interpretation, the interpreter should aim at optimizing the rationality of agents is defended. A distinction and a parallel is drawn between linguistic interpretation and psychological interpretation. Both can be taken to be governed, in part, and in somewhat different ways, by a principle of rationality. Such approaches have been criticised on the ground that they make it impossible for a speaker or an agent to have wildly irrational or false beliefs. It is argued that…Read more
  •  41
    This paper asks whether Brandom (1994) has provided a sufficiently clear account of the basic normative concepts of commitment and entitlement, on which his normative inferentialism seems to rest, and of how they contribute to explain the inferential articulation of conceptual contents. I show that Brandom's claim that these concepts are analogous to the concepts of obligation and permission cannot be right, and argue that the normative character of the concept of commitment is dubious. This lea…Read more
  •  3
    Essaies sur le language et l'intentionalité (edited book)
    with F. Lepage
    Bellarmin/Vrin. 1992.
  •  20
    Between Phenomenalism and Objectivism
    Journal of Philosophical Research 30 189-214. 2005.
    Brandom (1994) claims to have succeeded in showing how certain kinds of social practices can institute objective deontic statuses and confer objective conceptual contents on certain performances. This paper proposes a reconstruction of how, on Brandom’s views, this is supposed to come about, and a critical examination of the explicit arguments offered in support for this claim.
  •  23
    L'analyse théologique du contenu intentionnel
    Revue Philosophique De Louvain 96 (4): 660-690. 1998.
  •  41
    Réponses à mes critiques
    Philosophiques 30 (2): 421-424. 2003.
  •  12
    Pragmatics, Pittsburgh style
    Pragmatics and Cognition 13 (1): 141-160. 2005.
    I give a rough outline of Brandom’s scorekeeping account of conceptual content. The account is meant to be phenomenalist, normativist, expressively complete and non-circular; the question is how and to what extent it succeeds in meeting these goals.
  •  59
    ABSTRACT: I explain and rebut four objections to the claim that attributions of intentional attitudes are normative judgments, all stemming, directly or indirectly, from the widespread assumption that the normative supervenes on the non-normative
  •  73
    Nonconceptual contents vs nonconceptual states
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1): 23-43. 2005.
    The question to be discussed is whether the distinction between the conceptual and the nonconceptual is best understood as pertaining primarily to intentional contents or to intentional states or attitudes. Some authors have suggested that it must be understood in the second way, in order to make the claim that experiences are nonconceptual compatible with the idea that one can also believe what one experiences. I argue that there is no need to do so, and that a conceptual content can be underst…Read more
  •  35
    Mind-Dependence, Irrealism and Superassertibility
    Philosophia Scientae 12 (1): 143-157. 2008.
    Dans la section 1, j’explique pourquoi une conception Dummet-tienne du réalisme n’a de pertinence que dans certains cas particuliers. Dans la section 2, j’indique qu’il est raisonnable de penser que Crispin Wright soutient que la vérité de certains jugements dépend de notre capacité de la connaître (si et) seulement si leur vérité consiste dans le fait qu’ils sont superassertables. Dans la section 3, je souligne qu’insister, avec Dummett et Wright, sur la connaissabilité, nous empêche de voir qu…Read more
  •  29
    Tarski, Davidson et la signification
    Dialogue 22 (4): 595-620. 1983.
    Depuis 1967, Donald Davidson defend l'idée qu'une théorie de la signification pour une langue naturelle doit prendre la forme d'une théorie tarskienne de la vérité. Je me propose ici d'exposer les grandes lignes de l a conception davidsonienne de la sémantique des langues naturelles et de chercher à préciser en quel sens une theorie tarskienne de la vérité pour une langue L constitue, selon Davidson, une théorié de la signification pour L. Je ferai pour cela abstraction des obstacles qu'il pourr…Read more
  •  78
    I clarify in what sense one might want to claim that thought or language are public. I distinguish among four forms that each of these claims might take, and two general ways of establishing them that might be contemplated. The first infers the public character of thought from the public character of language, and the second infers the latter from the former. I show that neither of these stategies seems to be able to dispense with the claim that thought and language are interdependent, and that …Read more
  •  9
    Rationality and Intentionality
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 43 (1): 125-141. 1992.
    The view that in radical interpretation, the interpreter should aim at optimizing the rationality of agents is defended. A distinction and a parallel is drawn between linguistic interpretation and psychological interpretation. Both can be taken to be governed, in part, and in somewhat different ways, by a principle of rationality. Such approaches have been criticised on the ground that they make it impossible for a speaker or an agent to have wildly irrational or false beliefs. It is argued that…Read more