•  34
    Commentary on towards a design-based analysis of emotional episodes
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (2): 127-128. 1996.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Towards a Design-Based Analysis of Emotional Episodes”Dan Lloyd (bio)To think about grief is to think about many things. My one-year-old daughter was practicing opening and closing a cabinet door as I puzzled over a response to Wright, Sloman, and Beaudoin’s “Toward a Design-Based Analysis of Emotional Episodes.” She was completely absorbed in her project, and as I watched my elf at her task, I thought about the voices…Read more
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 96 (384): 583-588. 1987.
  •  34
    Access denied
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2): 261-262. 1995.
    The information processing that constitutes accessconsciousness is not sufficient to make a representational state conscious in any sense. Standard examples of computation without consciousness undermine A-consciousness, and Block's cases seem to derive their plausibility from a lurking phenomenal awareness. That is, people and other minded systems seem to have access-consciousness only insofar as the state accessed is a phenomenal one, or the state resulting from access is phenomenal, or both.
  •  19
    Simple Minds
    Philosophical Review 103 (4): 718. 1994.
  •  23
  •  26
    The scope and ingenuity of evolutionary systems
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3): 368-369. 1983.
  •  81
    Terra cognita: From functional neuroimaging to the map of the mind (review)
    Brain and Mind 1 (1): 93-116. 2000.
    For more than a century the paradigm inspiringcognitive neuroscience has been modular and localist.Contemporary research in functional brain imaginggenerally relies on methods favorable to localizingparticular functions in one or more specific brainregions. Meanwhile, connectionist cognitive scientistshave celebrated the computational powers ofdistributed processing, and pioneered methods forinterpreting distributed representations. This papertakes a connectionist approach to functionalneuroimag…Read more
  •  60
    Through a Glass Darkly: Schizophrenia and Functional Brain Imaging
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 18 (4): 257-274. 2011.
    To william james, conscious life was a stream; to Edmund Husserl, a flow. These metaphors point to the marvelous continuity of experience as it weaves through the world of thought and things. We might similarly talk about the flow of the body, as I reach for my cup of coffee. A physiologist could decompose the action, isolating the contribution of each muscle and joint to the whole. This functional analysis would constitute one form of explanation of the movement. As we replace "I grab the cup" …Read more
  •  85
    Studying the mind from the inside out
    Brain and Mind 3 (1): 243-59. 2002.
    Good research requires, among other virtues,(i) methods that yield stable experimentalobservations without arbitrary (post hoc)assumptions, (ii) logical interpretations ofthe sources of observations, and (iii) soundinferences to general causal mechanismsexplaining experimental results by placing themin larger explanatory contexts. In TheNew Phrenology , William Uttal examines theresearch tradition of localization, and findsit deficient in all three virtues, whetherbased on lesion studies or on n…Read more
  •  78
    Simple Minds
    MIT Press. 1989.
    Drawing on philosophy, neuroscience, and artificial intelligence, Simple Minds explores the construction of the mind from the matter of the brain.
  •  42
    Neural correlates of temporality: Default mode variability and temporal awareness
    Consciousness and Cognition 21 (2): 695-703. 2012.
    The continual background awareness of duration is an essential structure of consciousness, conferring temporal extension to the many objects of awareness within the evanescent sensory present. Seeking the possible neural correlates of ubiquitous temporal awareness, this article reexamines fMRI data from off-task “default mode” periods in 25 healthy subjects studied by Grady et al. , 2005). “Brain reading” using support vector machines detected information specifying elapsed time, and further ana…Read more
  •  9
    Many times over: A brief reply to Lee and Klincewicz
    Consciousness and Cognition 21 (2): 711-712. 2012.
  •  20
    Microcognition
    with Andy Clark
    Philosophical Review 101 (3): 706. 1992.
  •  67
    Is "Cognitive Neuroscience" an Oxymoron?
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 18 (4): 283-286. 2011.
    Could "cognitive neuroscience" be an oxymoron? "Cognitive" and "neuroscience" cohere only to the extent that the entities identified as "cognitive" can be coordinated with entities identified as neural. This coordination is typically construed as intertheoretic reduction between "levels" of scientific description. On the cognitive side, folk psychological concepts crystallize into behavioral taxonomies, which are further analyzed into purported cognitive capacities. These capacities are expresse…Read more
  •  26
    Double trouble for gestalt bubbles
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (4): 417-418. 2003.
    The “Gestalt Bubble” model of Lehar is not supported by the evidence offered. The author invalidly concludes that spatial properties in experience entail an explicit volumetric spatial representation in the brain. The article also exaggerates the extent to which phenomenology reveals a completely three-dimensional scene in perception.
  •  42
    Consciousness should not mean, but be
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (1): 158-159. 1999.
    O'Brien & Opie's vehicle hypothesis is an attractive framework for the study of consciousness. To fully embrace the hypothesis, however, two of the authors' claims should be extended: first, since phenomenal content is entirely dependent on occurrent brain events and only contingently correlated with external events, it is no longer necessary to regard states of consciousness as representations. Second, the authors' insistence that only stable states of a neural network are conscious seems ad ho…Read more
  •  67
    Commentary on Searle and the 'Deep Unconscious'
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (3): 201-202. 1996.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on “Searle and the ‘Deep Unconscious’”Dan Lloyd (bio)Can another person know my thoughts with better authority than I know them myself? With his affirmative answer to this question, Freud invented the twentieth-century human, a being whose mind is accessible to scrutiny from outside, and whose attempts at conscious self-explanation are at best partial and in many cases wrong. Even as Freud’s scientific influence wanes, the…Read more
  •  40
    Accounting for phenomenal structure—the forms, aspects, and features of conscious experience—poses a deep challenge for the scientific study of consciousness, but rather than abandon hope I propose a way forward. Connectionism, I argue, offers a bi-directional analogy, with its oft-noted “neural inspiration” on the one hand, and its largely unnoticed capacity to illuminate our phenomenology on the other. Specifically, distributed representations in a recurrent network enable networks to superpos…Read more
  •  84
    Consciousness: A connectionist manifesto (review)
    Minds and Machines 5 (2): 161-85. 1995.
      Connectionism and phenomenology can mutually inform and mutually constrain each other. In this manifesto I outline an approach to consciousness based on distinctions developed by connectionists. Two core identities are central to a connectionist theory of consciouness: conscious states of mind are identical to occurrent activation patterns of processing units; and the variable dispositional strengths on connections between units store latent and unconscious information. Within this broad frame…Read more
  •  59
    A novel theory
    The Philosophers' Magazine 26 (26): 49-50. 2004.