•  237
    Color constancy and the complexity of color
    Philosophical Topics 33 (1): 141-158. 2005.
    We can start with a definition. “[C]olour constancy is the constancy of the perceived colours of surfaces under changes in the intensity and spectral composition of the illumination.” (Foster et al. 1997) Given the definition we can now ask a question: Does human color vision exhibit color constancy?1 The answer to the question depends in part on how we interpret it. If the question is understood as asking whether human color vision displays constancy for every possible scene across every possib…Read more
  •  11
    Erster Teil Die übliche Auffassung von der Mathematik und ihre Widerlegung.- 1 Die Rolle von Anschauung und Erfahrung.- 2 Die Rolle der Voraussetzungen.- 3 Die Nichtuntrüglichkeit des mathematischen Schliessens.- Zweiter Teil Die landläufige Auffassung von der Physik und ihre Berichtigung.- 4 Physikalische Begriffsbildungen.- 5 Die Gesetze der Physik und ewige Naturgesetze.- 6 Die Beziehung zwischen Theorie und Experiment.- Dritter Teil Fragen philosophischen Charakters.- 7 Physikalische Gesetzl…Read more
  •  1
    Vision
    In Mohan Matthen (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the Philosophy of Perception, Oxford University Press Uk. 2015.
  •  8
    The Geometry of Vision and the Mind Body Problem (review)
    Philosophical Review 100 (2): 293-297. 1991.
  •  1014
    The science of color and color vision
    with Alex Byrne
    In Derek H. Brown & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Colour, Routledge. 2021.
    A survey of color science and color vision.
  •  726
    Objectivist reductionism
    with Alex Byrne
    In Derek H. Brown & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Colour, Routledge. 2021.
    A survey of arguments for and against the view that colors are physical properties.
  •  59
    A Naïve Realist Theory of Colour (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 (2): 408-411. 2019.
    Volume 97, Issue 2, June 2019, Page 408-411.
  •  18
    No problem
    with Colin Klein
    8 page
  • The Objectivity of Color
    Dissertation, Stanford University. 1987.
    Color has often been supposed to be a subjective property: a property which has its correct analysis in terms of phenomenological aspects of human experience. The most influential form of subjectivism with respect to color has been the dispositional analysis of Locke and Newton. On this view the color of an object is analyzed in terms of its disposition to produce certain kinds of experiences. ;In contrast with subjectivism an objectivist analysis of color takes color to be a property objects po…Read more
  •  323
    Do we see more than we can access?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (5-6): 501-502. 2007.
    Short commentary on a paper by Ned Block
  •  197
    Groups in Mind
    Philosophy of Science 73 (5): 765-777. 2006.
    We consider the question of the manner of the internalization of the geometry and topology of physical space in the mind, both the mechanism of internalization and precisely what structures are internalized. Though we will not argue for the point here, we agree with the long tradition which holds that an understanding of this issue is crucial for addressing many metaphysical and epistemological questions concerning space
  •  605
    Color and the inverted spectrum
    In Steven Davis (ed.), Vancouver Studies in Cognitive Science, Oxford University Press. pp. 187-214. 2000.
    If you trained someone to emit a particular sound at the sight of something red, another at the sight of something yellow, and so on for other colors, still he would not yet be describing objects by their colors. Though he might be a help to us in giving a description. A description is a representation of a distribution in a space (in that of time, for instance).
  •  84
    Readings on Color I: The Philosophy of Color (edited book)
    with Alex Byrne
    MIT Press. 1997.
    Edward Wilson Averill By the phrase 'anthropocentric account of color' I mean an account of color that makes an assumption of the following form: two ...
  •  358
    What is color vision?
    Philosophical Studies 68 (3): 351-70. 1992.
    There are serious reasons for accepting each of these propositions individually but there are apparently insurmountable difficulties with accepting all three of them simultaneously if we assume that color is a single property. 1) and 2) together seem to imply that there is some property which all organisms with color vision can see and 3) seems to imply that there can be no such property. If these implications really are valid then one or more of these propositions will have to be rejected in sp…Read more
  •  56
    Glossary of color science
    with Alex Byrne
    In A. Byrne & D. R. Hilbert (eds.), Readings on Color, Volume 2: The Science of Color, Mit Press. 1997.
    Anomaloscope An instrument used for detecting anomalies of color vision. The test subject adjusts the ratio of two monochromatic lights to form a match with a third monochromatic light. The most common form of this procedure involves a Rayleigh match: a match between a mixture of monochromatic green and red lights, and a monochromatic yellow light. Normal subjects will choose a matching ratio of red to green light that falls within a fairly narrow range of values. Subjects with anomalous color v…Read more
  •  35
    Is Seeing Believing?
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994. 1994.
    One of the traditional problems of philosophy is the nature of the connection between perceptual experience and empirical knowledge. That there is an intimate connection between the two is rarely doubted. Three case studies of visual deficits due to brain damage are used to motivate the claim that perceptual experience is neither necessary nor sufficient for perceptual knowledge. Acceptance of this claim leaves a mystery as to the epistemic role, if any, of perceptual experience. It is argued th…Read more
  •  54
    Comments on anthropomorphism
    Philosophical Studies 69 (2-3): 123-127. 1993.
  •  70
    Urban Light and Color
    with Alex Byrne
    New Geographies 3 64-71. 2011.
    In Colour for Architecture, published in 1976, the editors, Tom Porter and Byron Mikellides, explain that their book was “produced out of an awareness that colour, as a basic and vital force, is lacking from the built environment and that our knowledge of it is isolated and limited.”1 Lack of urban color was then especially salient in Britain—where the book was published—which had just begun to recoil at the Brutalist legacy of angular stained gray concrete strewn across the postwar landscape. P…Read more
  •  180
    Philosophical issues about colour vision
    with Alex Byrne
    In L. Nagel (ed.), Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science, Macmillan. 2002.
    The primary issues concern whether objects have colours, and what sorts of properties the colours are. Some philosophers hold that nothing is coloured, others that colour are powers to affect perceivers, and others that colours are physical properties.
  •  12
    The Geometry of Vision and the Mind Body Problem (review)
    with Robert E. French
    Philosophical Review 100 (2): 293. 1991.
  •  790
    Color relationalism and relativism
    with Alex Byrne
    Topics in Cognitive Science 9 (1): 172-192. 2017.
    This paper critically examines color relationalism and color relativism, two theories of color that are allegedly supported by variation in normal human color vision. We mostly discuss color relationalism, defended at length in Jonathan Cohen's The Red and the Real, and argue that the theory has insuperable problems.
  •  781
    How do things look to the color-blind?
    with Alex Byrne
    In Jonathan Cohen & Mohan Matthen (eds.), Color Ontology and Color Science, Mit Press. pp. 259. 2010.
    Color-vision defects constitute a spectrum of disorders with varying degrees and types of departure from normal human color vision. One form of color-vision defect is dichromacy; by mixing together only two lights, the dichromat can match any light, unlike normal trichromatic humans, who need to mix three. In a philosophical context, our titular question may be taken in two ways. First, it can be taken at face value as a question about visible properties of external objects, and second, it may b…Read more
  •  81
    Constancy, Content, and Inference
    In Gary Hatfield & Sarah Allred (eds.), Visual Experience: Sensation, Cognition, and Constancy, Oxford University Press. pp. 199. 2012.
  •  435
    Truest blue
    with A. Byrne
    Analysis 67 (1): 87-92. 2007.
    1. The “puzzle” Physical objects are coloured: roses are red, violets are blue, and so forth. In particular, physical objects have fine-grained shades of colour: a certain chip, we can suppose, is true blue (unique, or pure blue). The following sort of scenario is commonplace. The chip looks true blue to John; in the same (ordinary) viewing conditions it looks (slightly) greenish-blue to Jane. Both John and Jane are “normal” perceivers. Now, nothing can be both true blue and greenish-blue; since…Read more
  •  146
    Hoffman’s “proof” of the possibility of spectrum inversion
    with Alex Byrne
    Consciousness and Cognition 15 (1): 48-50. 2006.
    Philosophers have devoted a great deal of discussion to the question of whether an inverted spectrum thought experiment refutes functionalism. (For a review of the inverted spectrum and its many philosophical applications, see Byrne, 2004.) If Ho?man is correct the matter can be swiftly and conclusively settled, without appeal to any empirical data about color vision (or anything else). Assuming only that color experiences and functional relations can be mathematically represented, a simple math…Read more
  •  100
    Qualia
    In Gibson Bruce (ed.), Sage Encyclopedia of Perception, Sage Publishing. 2010.
    Perception and thought are often, although not exclusively, concerned with information about the world. In the case of perceiving though, unlike thinking, it is widely believed that there is an additional element involved, a subjective feeling or, as it is often put, something that it is like to be perceiving. Qualia are these characteristic feelings that accompany perceiving. One motivation for the idea that we experience qualia is that there is a clear difference between seeing a red tomato an…Read more
  •  242
    Basic sensible qualities and the structure of appearance
    with Alex Byrne
    Philosophical Issues 18 (1): 385-405. 2008.
    A sensible quality is a perceptible property, a property that physical objects (or events) perceptually appear to have. Thus smells, tastes, colors and shapes are sensible qualities. An egg, for example, may smell rotten, taste sour, and look cream and round.1,2 The sensible qualities are not a miscellanous jumble—they form complex structures. Crimson, magenta, and chartreuse are not merely three different shades of color: the first two are more similar than either is to the third. Familiar colo…Read more
  •  486
    Color Primitivism
    with Alex Byrne
    Erkenntnis 66 (1-2). 2006.
    The typical kind of color realism is reductive: the color properties are identified with properties specified in other terms (as ways of altering light, for instance). If no reductive analysis is available — if the colors are primitive sui generis properties — this is often taken to be a convincing argument for eliminativism. That is, realist primitivism is usually thought to be untenable. The realist preference for reductive theories of color over the last few decades is particularly striking i…Read more
  •  44
    Basic tastes and unique hues
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (1): 82-82. 2008.
    The logic of the basic taste concept is discussed in relation to the physiology and psychophysics of color vision. An alternative version of the basic taste model, analogous to opponent-process theory is introduced. The logic of quality naming experiments is clarified