•  8275
    Divided minds and the nature of persons
    In Colin Blakemore & Susan A. Greenfield (eds.), Mindwaves, Blackwell. pp. 19-26. 1987.
  •  6052
    Overpopulation and the Quality of Life
    In Peter Singer (ed.), Applied Ethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 145-164. 1986.
    How many people should there be? Can there be overpopulation: too many people living? I shall present a puzzling argument about these questions, show how this argument can be strengthened, then sketch a possible reply.
  •  1686
    Reasons and Persons
    Oxford University Press. 1984.
    Challenging, with several powerful arguments, some of our deepest beliefs about rationality, morality, and personal identity, Parfit claims that we have a false view about our own nature. It is often rational to act against our own best interersts, he argues, and most of us have moral views that are self-defeating. We often act wrongly, although we know there will be no one with serious grounds for complaint, and when we consider future generations it is very hard to avoid conclusions that most …Read more
  •  1589
    We Are Not Human Beings
    Philosophy 87 (1): 5-28. 2012.
    We can start with some science fiction. Here on Earth, I enter the Teletransporter. When I press some button, a machine destroys my body, while recording the exact states of all my cells. This information is sent by radio to Mars, where another machine makes, out of organic materials, a perfect copy of my body. The person who wakes up on Mars seems to remember living my life up to the moment when I pressed the button, and is in every other way just like me.
  •  1069
    "From the Proceedings of the British Academy, London, volume LXV (1979)" - title page. Series: Henrietta Hertz Trust annual philosophical lecture -- 1978 Other Titles: Proceedings of the British Academy. Vol.65: 1979.
  •  837
    When Ingmar and I discuss metaphysics or morality, our views are seldom far apart. Hut on the subjects of this paper, rationality and reasons, we deeply disagree
  •  834
    Reasons and motivation
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 71 (1). 1997.
    When we have a normative reason, and we act for that reason, it becomes our motivating reason. But we can have either kind of reason without having the other. Thus, if I jump into the canal, my motivating reason was provided by my belief; but I had no normative reason to jump. I merely thought I did. And, if I failed to notice that the canal was frozen, I had a reason not to jump that, because it was unknown to me, did not motivate me. Though we can have normative reasons without being motivated…Read more
  •  826
    The unimportance of identity
    In H. Harris (ed.), Identity, Oxford University Press. pp. 13-45. 1995.
    We can start with some science fiction. Here on Earth, I enter the Teletransporter. When I press some button, a machine destroys my body, while recording the exact states of all my cells. The information is sent by radio to Mars, where another machine makes, out of organic materials, a perfect copy of my body. The person who wakes up on Mars seems to remember living my life up to the moment when I pressed the button, and he is in every other way just like me. Of those who have thought about such…Read more
  •  675
    Personal identity and rationality
    Synthese 53 (2): 227-241. 1982.
    There are two main views about the nature of personal identity. I shall briehy describe these views, say without argument which I believe to be true, and then discuss the implications of this view for one of the main conceptions of rationality. This conception I shall call "C1assical Prudence." I shall argue that, on what I believe to be the true view about personal identity, Classical Prudence is indefensible.
  •  666
    Overpopulation and the quality of life
    In J. Ryberg & T. Tännsjö (eds.), The Repugnant Conclusion, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 7-22. 2004.
    How many people should there be? Can there be overpopulation: too many people living? I shall present a puzzling argument about these questions, show how this argument can be strengthened, then sketch a possible reply.
  •  664
    Future People, the Non‐Identity Problem, and Person‐Affecting Principles
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 45 (2): 118-157. 2017.
    Suppose we discover how we could live for a thousand years, but in a way that made us unable to have children. Everyone chooses to live these long lives. After we all die, human history ends, since there would be no future people. Would that be bad? Would we have acted wrongly? Some pessimists would answer No. These people are saddened by the suffering in most people’s lives, and they believe it would be wrong to inflict such suffering on others by having children. In earlier centuries, this ble…Read more
  •  595
    Lewis, Perry, and what matters
    In Amelie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons, University of California Press. 1976.
  •  588
    Equality or Priority?
    In Matthew Clayton & Andrew Williams (eds.), The Ideal of Equality, Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 81-125. 2002.
    One of the central debates within contemporary Anglo-American political philosophy concerns how to formulate an egalitarian theory of distributive justice which gives coherent expression to egalitarian convictions and withstands the most powerful anti-egalitarian objections. This book brings together many of the key contributions to that debate by some of the world’s leading political philosophers: Richard Arneson, G.A. Cohen, Ronald Dworkin, Thomas Nagel, Derek Parfit, John Rawls, T.M. Scanlon,…Read more
  •  462
    Can We Avoid the Repugnant Conclusion?
    Theoria 82 (2): 110-127. 2016.
    According to the Repugnant Conclusion: Compared with the existence of many people who would all have some very high quality of life, there is some much larger number of people whose existence would be better, even though these people would all have lives that were barely worth living. I suggest some ways in which we might be able to avoid this conclusion. I try to defend a strong form of lexical superiority.
  •  446
    Future generations: Further problems
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 11 (2): 113-172. 1982.
  •  420
    Justifiability to each person
    Ratio 16 (4). 2003.
    sonable, in this sense, if we ignore, or give too little weight to, some other people's well-being or moral claims.' Some critics have suggested that, because Scanlon appeals to this sense of 'reasonable', his formula is empty. On this objection, whenever we believe that some act is wrong, we shall believe that people have moral claims not to be treated in this way. We could therefore argue that such acts are disallowed by some principle which no one could reasonably reject, since anyone who rej…Read more
  •  412
    On What Matters: Two-Volume Set
    Oxford University Press. 2011.
    This is a major work in moral philosophy, the long-awaited follow-up to Parfit's 1984 classic Reasons and Persons, a landmark of twentieth-century philosophy. Parfit now presents a powerful new treatment of reasons and a critical examination of the most prominent systematic moral theories, leading to his own ground-breaking conclusion.
  •  369
    Innumerate ethics
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 7 (4): 285-301. 1978.
    Suppose that we can help either one person or many others. Is it a reason t0 help the many that We should thus be helping more people? John Taurek thinks not. We may learn from his arguments.
  •  354
    Another Defence of the Priority View
    Utilitas 24 (3): 399-440. 2012.
    This article discusses the relation between prioritarian and egalitarian principles, whether and why we need to appeal to both kinds of principle, how prioritarians can answer various objections, especially those put forward by Michael Otsuka and Alex Voorhoeve, the moral difference between cases in which our acts could affect only one person or two or more people, veil of ignorance contractualism and utilitarianism, what prioritarians should claim about cases in which the effects of our acts ar…Read more
  •  323
    Why our identity is not what matters
    In Raymond Martin & John Barresi (eds.), Personal Identity, Blackwell. pp. 115--143. 2003.
    Presents actual cases of brain bisection; how we might be able to divide and reunite our minds; what explains the unity of consciousness at any time; the imagined case of full division, in which each half of our brain would be successfully transplanted into the empty skull of another body; why neither of the resulting people would be us; why this would not matter, since our relation to each of these people contains what matters in the prudential sense, giving us reasons to care about these peopl…Read more
  •  312
    Why Does the Universe Exist?
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 1 (1): 4-5. 1991.
  •  240
    Is common-sense morality self-defeating?
    Journal of Philosophy 76 (10): 533-545. 1979.
    When is a moral theory self-defeating? I suggest the following. There are certain things we ought to try to achieve. Call these our moral aims. Our moral theory would be self-defeating if we believed we ought to do what will cause our moral aims to be worse achieved. Is this ever true? If so, what does it show?
  •  147
    Experiences, subjects, and conceptual schemes
    Philosophical Topics 26 (1-2): 217-70. 1999.