•  171
    My aim in this paper is to provide an effective counterexample to consequentialism. I assume that traditional counterexamples, such as Transplant (A doctor should kill one person and transplant her organs to five terminal patients, thereby saving their lives) and Judge (A judge should sentence to death an innocent person if he knows that an outraged mob will otherwise kill many innocent persons), are not effective, for two reasons: first, they make unrealistic assumptions and, second, they do no…Read more
  •  105
    Can There Be Full Excuses for Morally Wrong Actions?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 73 (1): 124-142. 2007.
    Most people (and philosophers) distinguish between performing a morally wrong action and being blameworthy for having performed that action, and believe that an individual can be fully excused for having performed a wrong action. My purpose is to reject this claim. More precisely, I defend what I call the “Dependence Claim”: A's doing X is wrong only if A is blameworthy for having done X. I consider three cases in which, according to the traditional view, a wrong action could be excused: duress,…Read more
  •  97
    Organ Sales and Moral Distress
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (1): 41-52. 2006.
    abstract The possibility that organ sales by living adults might be made legal is morally distressing to many of us. However, powerful arguments have been provided recently supporting legalisation (I consider two of those arguments: the Consequentialist Argument and the Autonomy Argument). Is our instinctive reaction against a market of organs irrational then? The aim of this paper is not to prove that legalization would be immoral, all things considered, but rather to show, first, that there ar…Read more
  •  93
    Probabilities in tragic choices
    Utilitas 20 (3): 323-333. 2008.
    In this article I explore a kind of tragic choice that has not received due attention, one in which you have to save only one of two persons but the probability of saving is not equal (and all other things are equal). Different proposals are assessed, taking as models proposals for a much more discussed tragic choice situation: saving different numbers of persons. I hold that cases in which (only) numbers are different are structurally similar to cases in which (only) probabilities are different…Read more
  •  92
    Individual procreative responsibility and the non-identity problem
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (3): 336-363. 2009.
    The question I address in this paper is whether and under what conditions it is morally right to bring a person into existence. I defend the commonsensical thesis that, other things being equal, it is morally wrong to create a person who will be below some threshold of quality of life, even if the life of this potential person, once created, will nevertheless be worth living. However commonsensical this view might seem, it has shown to be problematic because of the so-called 'Non-Identity Proble…Read more
  •  87
    Are Mental State Welfarism and Our Concern for Non‐Experiential Goals Incompatible?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (1): 74-91. 2007.
    The question I address in this paper is whether there is a version of mental state welfarism that can be coherent with the thesis that we have a legitimate concern for non‐experiential goals. If there is not, then we should reject mental state welfarism. My thesis is that there is such a version. My argument relies on the distinction between “reality‐centered desires” and “experience‐centered desires”. Mental state welfarism can accommodate our reality‐centered desires and our desire that they b…Read more
  •  64
    Is it Morally Wrong to Defend Unjust Causes as a Lawyer?
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 32 (2): 177-189. 2014.
    The question I address in this article is whether it is morally wrong for a lawyer to represent a client whose purpose is immoral or unjust. My answer to this question is that it is wrong, prima facie. This conclusion holds, even accepting certain traditional principles of lawyer's professional ethics, such as the right of defence and the so-called principle of ‘adversarial’ litigation. Both the adversarial system and the right of defence are sufficient to support or justify the right of potenti…Read more
  •  62
    How to Reject Resultant Moral Luck Alone
    Journal of Value Inquiry 50 (2): 415-423. 2016.
  •  52
    The Fragility of our Moral Standing to Blame
    Ethical Perspectives 24 (3): 333-361. 2017.
  •  45
  •  35
    Puzzles on defending others from aggression
    Law and Philosophy 25 (3): 377-386. 2005.
    We all agree on the justification of defending ourselves or others in some situations, but we do not often agree on why. Two main views compete: subjectivism and objectivism. The discussion has mainly been held in normative terms. But every theory must pass a previous test: logical consistency. It has recently been held that, at least in the case of defending others from aggression, objective theories lead, in some situations, to normative contradiction. My aim is to challenge the idea that only…Read more
  •  29
    Kommunitaristische Paradoxe
    Analyse & Kritik 17 (2): 149-166. 1995.
    Two basic kinds of communitarians are discriminated. Weak communitarians reject only the liberal metaethical theses that I call universalism and neutralism, but endorse liberal norms and institutions at the normative level. Strong communitarians condemn liberalism at both levels: they reject not only universalism and neutralism, but also substantive liberal norms defending communitarian values. This article intends to show certain internal paradoxes of these two versions of communitarianism
  •  26
    Against the Evidence-Relative View of Liability to Defensive Harm
    with Luciano Venezia
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 18 (1): 45-60. 2024.
    According to the evidence-relative view of liability to defensive harm, a person is so liable if and only if she acts in a way that provides sufficient evidence to justify a (putative) victim’s belief that the person poses a threat of unjust harm, which may or may not be the case. Bas van der Vossen defends this position by analyzing, in relation to a version of Frank Jackson’s famous drug example, a case in which a putative murderer is killed by a putative victim. Van der Vossen submits that th…Read more
  •  25
    The claim from adoption revisited
    Bioethics 20 (6). 2006.
    ABSTRACT In a recent paper published in this journal, Thomas S. Petersen makes a qualified defense of what he calls ‘the Claim from Adoption’, according to which, ‘instead of expending resources on bringing new children [in developed countries] into the world using reproductive technology and caring for these children, we ought to devote these resources to the adoption and care of existing destitute children’. My purpose in this paper is not to discuss Petersen’s argument in favor of that claim.…Read more
  •  24
    What Does Nozick’s Experience Machine Argument Really Prove?
    The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 40 100-105. 1998.
    Nozick's well-known Experience Machine argument can be considered a typically successful argument: as far as I know, it has not been discussed much and has been widely seen as conclusive, or at least convincing enough to refute the mental-state versions of utilitarianism. I believe that if his argument were conclusive, its destructive effect would be even stronger. It would not only refute mental-state utilitarianism, but all theories considering a certain subjective mental state as the only val…Read more
  •  23
    Ethics and Genetics in Latin America
    Developing World Bioethics 2 (1): 11-20. 2002.
    Genetic research in human beings poses deep ethical problems, one being the problem of distributive justice. If we suppose that genetic technologies are able to produce visible benefits for the well being of people, and that these benefits are affordable to only a favored portion of society, then the consequence is obvious. We are introducing a new source of inequality. In the first section of this paper, I attempt to justify some concern for the distributive consequences of applying genetics to…Read more
  •  18
    What is the Role of Partial Compliance in Moral Theory?
    Journal of Value Inquiry 1-13. forthcoming.
    The problem of nonideal theory has been widely discussed in political philosophy in recent times. The problem has received much less attention, however, at the level of individual morality. Since the real world is a nonideal one, the problem is extremely relevant, if moral theory is to guide our action as moral agents. My purpose in this paper is mainly conceptual. I first clarify the distinction between different kinds of nonideal situation (natural accidents or limitations and partial complian…Read more
  •  17
    Is medically assisted death a special obligation?
    Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (6): 401-406. 2017.
  •  17
    Euthanasia, consensual homicide, and refusal of treatment
    Bioethics 38 (4): 292-299. 2024.
    Consensual homicide remains a crime in jurisdictions where active voluntary euthanasia has been legalized. At the same time, both jurisdictions, in which euthanasia is legal and those in which it is not, recognize that all patients (whether severely ill or not) have the right to refuse or withdraw medical treatment (including life-saving treatment). In this paper, I focus on the tensions between these three norms (the permission of active euthanasia, the permission to reject life-saving treatmen…Read more
  •  15
    In this article we identify three previously unnoticed problems with flexible moral theories, i.e., theories according to which different moral rules apply when there is full compliance and when there is partial compliance. The first problem is that flexible theories are necessarily very complex, which undermines their ability to motivate and guide action. The second problem is that flexible theories allow for a troubling kind of (moral) domination: the duties an agent has depend on other agents…Read more
  •  12
    Consent and Exploitation in Bioethics: Individual Ethics and Legal Regulation
    In Eduardo Rivera-López & Martin Hevia (eds.), Controversies in Latin American Bioethics, Springer Verlag. pp. 83-95. 2019.
    In this paper, I discuss exploitative transactions in bioethics. Examples of this kind of transactions allegedly include, among others, commercial surrogacy, organ selling, and research with human subjects in developing countries. The most problematic kind of exploitation is what Allan Wertheimer calls “mutually advantageous exploitation:” the weak party’s consent for the transaction is an effective and rational consent. Moreover, W does not suffer any harm by the transaction; on the contrary, t…Read more
  •  11
    Social Rights and Deontological Constraints
    Law Ethics and Philosophy 6. 2019.
  •  9
    Introduction: Why (and How) Bioethics Matters in Latin America
    In Eduardo Rivera-López & Martin Hevia (eds.), Controversies in Latin American Bioethics, Springer Verlag. pp. 1-8. 2019.
    Bioethics embraces a number of ethical problems connected to medicine, biomedical research, and health law. Most of these have both a universal dimension and a more particular one. Reproductive rights, exploitation, commodification, biomedical research, and the protection of the environment, among others, are issues that can be discussed from a universal perspective.
  •  7
    Nonideal Ethics (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2013.
  •  6
    Social Rights and Deontological Constraints
    Law, Ethics and Philosophy 6. 2019.
  •  5
    Contemporary ethics and political philosophy
    In Susana Nuccetelli, Ofelia Schutte & Otávio Bueno (eds.), A Companion to Latin American Philosophy, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Metaethics: The Foundations of Moral Values and Norms Normative Principles: Human Rights and Democracy Applications: Bioethics and Multiculturalism Conclusion References.
  •  5
    According to the World Bank, 767 million people, 10.7 percent of the world’s population, live on less than 1.9 dollars a day, and around 2 billion, 28,7 percent of humankind, on less than 3.2 dollars a day.1 About 815 million are undernourished. About 155 million children will suffer from stunted growth.
  • Ethics and political philosophy
    In Susana Nuccetelli, Ofelia Schutte & Otávio Bueno (eds.), A Companion to Latin American Philosophy, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  • “ Moral luck” alludes to the fact of being responsible for things over which we have no control. Typically, we have neither control over the consequences of our acts of will nor over the circumstances in which these acts are performed. The Kantian thesis on oral responsibility claims that every kind of moral responsibility claims that every kind of moral luck should be eliminated from our moral language and practice. In the case of consequences, this aim does not seem impossible. But circumstanc…Read more