•  5
    Hume's Theory of Justice
    Philosophical Quarterly 32 (129): 384-385. 1982.
  •  6
    Michael Williams and the hypothetical world
    Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 6 (1). 2002.
    Michael Williams has frequently considered and rejected approaches to "our knowledge of the external world" that see it as the best explanation for certain features of experience. This paper examines the salience of his position to approaches such as Mackie’s that do not deny the presentational directness of ordinary experience but do permit a gap between how things appear and how they are that allows for sceptical doubts. Williams’ main argument is that, to do justice to its place in a foundati…Read more
  •  7
    On What Isn't Learned in School
    Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 5 (4): 22-28. 1985.
  •  14
    Rationality and Paternalism
    Philosophy 57 (222): 533-536. 1982.
  •  7
    Quantifiers and the Pursuit of Truth
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 14 (1): 51-58. 1982.
  •  3
    The Key of the Door1
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 11 (1): 23-34. 1979.
  •  13
    Aptitude Analysed
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 17 (2): 13-18. 1985.
  • Michael Williams And The Hypothetical World
    Minerva 6 151-161. 2002.
    Michael Williams has frequently considered and rejected approaches to “our knowledge of the external world”that see it as the best explanation for certain features of experience.This paper examines the salience of his position to approaches such as Mackie’s that do not deny thepresentational directness of ordinary experience but do permit a gap between how things appear and how theyare that allows for sceptical doubts.Williams’ main argument is that, to do justice to its place in a foundationali…Read more
  •  72
    Is "A needs X" Elliptical?
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 45 125-134. 1993.
    While "A needs X" often calls for supplementation by the Y X is needed for, Thomson, Wiggins and Braybrooke have argued that there is a sense of "need" for which this is unnecessary. But Gricean conventions for conversation allow us to use ellipsis in a unified account of "need" while explaining the data Thomson and Wiggins appeal to: nondetatchment of bare needs from more fully specified ones, avoidance of serious harm as a default filling of the Y-slot, and the apparent normativeness of some n…Read more
  •  21
    The unjustifiability of education
    Studies in Philosophy and Education 14 (2-3): 217-227. 1995.
  •  8
    How to Choose the Best
    with J. Gingell
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (3): 443-460. 2000.
    This chapter deals with a crucial component of our position, the presumption that there are objective grounds for preferring one thing to another within the various cultural institutions we deal with, that there are better or worse symphonies, soufflés and theories of the atom. The task of showing this is more urgent for some institutions than others. While philosophers can doubt anything, most people are persuaded of the objectivity of our efforts to comprehend the physical world and to weigh, …Read more
  •  33
  •  13
    Do Teachers Care about Truth?
    British Journal of Educational Studies 36 (2): 177-178. 1988.
  •  80
    California Unnatural: On Fine’s Natural Ontological Attitude
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (187): 232-235. 1997.
    Abela accepts Fine’s account of realism and instrumentalism, but thinks that we can reject the Natural Ontological Attitude by distinguishing the theoretical attempt to make sense of scientific practice from choosing the attitude we bring to the debate, or to science itself. But Abela’s attitudes are vulnerable to Fine’s criticisms of the philosophical positions. However, if we take attitude as contrastive and as full‐blooded enough to lead to different behaviour we can see a gap in Fine’s posit…Read more
  •  6
    The Plurality of Cultures
    with J. Gingell
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (3): 507-523. 2000.
    Arnold wrote in an educational tradition that both lay in a main line of descent from the cultural formations he most valued and equipped him with the tools necessary to appreciate many of the elements in those traditions that are not in his native language. So when he referred, as exemplars of high culture, to Homer and Cicero, Montesquieu and Goethe, he presumed acquaintance with their works in the original languages on his own part and on that of his audience. His own vernacular derived from …Read more
  • William Sweet, ed., The Bases of Ethics Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 22 (5): 370-372. 2002.
  •  15
    Popular Culture
    with J. Gingell
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (3): 461-485. 2000.
    J. Gingell, E. P. Brandon; Popular Culture, Journal of Philosophy of Education, Volume 34, Issue 3, 7 March 2003, Pages 461–485, https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-97.
  •  21
    Ellipsis: History and Prospects
    Informal Logic 8 (2). 1986.
  •  5
    Preface
    with John Gingell
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (3): 5-5. 2000.
  •  13
    A Forerunner
    with J. Gingell
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (3): 401-414. 2000.
    In the course of this book we shall frequently appeal to what we call an Arnoldian filter, a principle we wish to urge for choosing much of what should form part of education in schools. This priniciple is based on a remark in Matthew Arnold's Preface to Culture and Anarchy,1 that culture is a matter of getting ‘to know, on all the matters which most concern us, the best which has been thought and said in the world’ (1935, p.6, emphasis added). Arnold's work here and elsewhere is often seen as a…Read more
  •  39
    Supposition, Conditionals and Unstated Premises
    Informal Logic 14 (2). 1992.
    Informal logicians recognise the frequent use of unstated assumptions; some (e.g. Fisher) also recognise entertained arguments and recommend a suppositional approach (such as Mackie's) to conditional statements. It is here argued that these two be put together to make argument diagrams more accurate and subtle. Philosophical benefits also accrue: insights into Jackson's apparent violations of modus tollens and contraposition and McGee's counterexamples to the validity of modus ponens
  •  3
    Dale Jacquette, Ontology Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 24 (2): 120-122. 2004.
  •  7
    Practical Implications
    with J. Gingell
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 34 (3): 525-531. 2000.
  •  8
    The Two Forms, the Two Attitudes, and the Four Kinds of Awareness
    Educational Philosophy and Theory 16 (1): 1-11. 1984.
  •  24
  •  53
    Subjectivism and seriousness
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (119): 97-107. 1980.