•  196
    Einstein’s 1935 Derivation of E=mc2
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 29 (2): 223-243. 1998.
    Einstein’s 1935 derivation of mass—energy equivalence is philosophically important because it contains both a criticism of purported demonstrations that proceed by analogy and strong motivations for the definitions of the ‘new’ dynamical quantities. In this paper, I argue that Einstein’s criticism and insights are still relevant today by showing how his derivation goes beyond Friedman’s demonstration of this result in his Foundations of Spacetime ¹heories. Along the way, I isolate three distinct…Read more
  •  111
    Interpretations of Einstein’s Equation E = mc 2
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (3): 245-260. 2005.
    Interpretations of Einstein’s equation differ primarily concerning whether E = mc2 entails that mass and energy are the same property of physical systems, and hence whether there is any sense in which mass is ever ‘converted’ into energy. In this paper, I examine six interpretations of Einstein’s equation and argue that all but one fail to satisfy a minimal set of conditions that all interpretations of physical theories ought to satisfy. I argue that we should prefer the interpretation of Einste…Read more
  •  108
    Einstein’s theory of theories and types of theoretical explanation
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (2). 1999.
    In this paper I draw on Einstein's distinction between “principle” and “constructive” theories to isolate two levels of physical theory that can be found in both classical and (special) relativistic physics. I then argue that when we focus on theoretical explanations in physics, i.e. explanations of physical laws, the two leading views on explanation, Salmon's “bottom-up” view and Kitcher's “top-down” view, accurately describe theoretical explanations for a given level of theory. I arrive at thi…Read more
  •  43
    On the Interpretation of the Equation E = mc 2: Response to Krajewski
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 20 (2): 217-218. 2006.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  32
    The equivalence of mass and energy
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  22
    Bell’s spaceship ‘paradox’ [1] in special relativity is a particularly good one to examine with students, because although it deals with accelerated motions, it can be dissolved with elementary space–time diagrams. Furthermore, it forces us to be very clear about the relativity of simultaneity, proper length, and the ‘reality’ of the Lorentz contraction
  •  8
    Our goal here is to determine the spatial and temporal constraints on communication between two observers at least one of which moves with constant proper acceleration in two-dimensional Minkowski spacetime. We take as a simplified model of communication one observer bouncing a light signal off another observer. Our derivations use only elementary mathematics and spacetime diagrams, and hence are accessible to students taking their first course in special relativity. Furthermore, the qualitative…Read more
  • Levels of Theory and Types of Theoretical Explanation in Theoretical Physics
    Dissertation, The University of Western Ontario (Canada). 1998.
    In Newtonian physics, there is a clear distinction between a "framework theory", a collection of general physical principles and definitions of physical terms, and theories that describe specific causal interactions such as gravitation, i.e., "interaction theories". I argue that this distinction between levels of theory can also be found in the context of Special Relativity and that recognizing it is essential for a philosophical account of how laws are explained in this theory. As a case study,…Read more