•  288
    Two Kinds of Mental Conflict in Republic IV
    History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 25 (2): 255-281. 2021.
    Plato’s partition argument infers that the soul has parts from the fact that the soul experiences mental conflict. We consider an ambiguity in the concept of mental conflict. According to the first sense of conflict, a soul is in conflict when it has desires whose satisfaction is logically incompatible. According to the second sense of conflict, a soul is in conflict when it has desires which are logically incompatible even when they are unsatisfied. This raises a dilemma: if the mental conflict…Read more
  •  379
    Facts vs. Opinions: Helping Students Overcome the Distinction
    Teaching Philosophy 45 (3): 267-277. 2022.
    Many students struggle to enter moral debates in a productive way because they automatically think of moral claims as ‘just opinions’ and not something one could productively argue about. Underlying this response are various versions of a muddled distinction between ‘facts’ and ‘opinions.’ This paper outlines a way to help students overcome their use of this distinction, thereby clearing an obstacle to true moral debate. It explains why the fact-opinion distinction should simply be scrapped, rat…Read more
  •  309
    Spinoza and Counterpossible Inferences
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 102 (1): 27-50. 2021.
    Spinoza reasons about impossibilities on a regular basis. But he also says they're unthinkable and that reasoning is a mental process. How can he do this? The paper defends a linguistic account of counterpossible inferences in Spinoza's geometrical method.
  •  345
    Spinoza on the resistance of bodies
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 86 (C): 56-67. 2021.
    People attribute resistance to bodies in Spinoza's physics. It's not always clear what they mean when they do this, or whether they are entitled to. This article clarifies what it would mean, and examines the evidence for attributing resistance. The verdict: there's some evidence, but not nearly as much as people think.
  •  576
    Morally Respectful Listening and its Epistemic Consequences
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 58 (1): 52-76. 2020.
    What does it mean to listen to someone respectfully, that is, insofar as they are due recognition respect? This paper addresses that question and gives the following answer: it is to listen in such a way that you are open to being surprised. A specific interpretation of this openness to surprise is then defended.
  •  617
    Spinoza and the Logical Limits of Mental Representation
    Journal of Modern Philosophy 1 (1): 5. 2019.
    This paper examines Spinoza’s view on the consistency of mental representation. First, I argue that he departs from Scholastic tradition by arguing that all mental states—whether desires, intentions, beliefs, perceptions, entertainings, etc.—must be logically consistent. Second, I argue that his endorsement of this view is motivated by key Spinozistic doctrines, most importantly the doctrine that all acts of thought represent what could follow from God’s nature. Finally, I argue that Spinoza’s v…Read more
  •  73
    Using Conway’s Game of Life to Teach Free Will
    Teaching Philosophy 41 (4): 337-347. 2018.
    The concept of determinism proves to be a persistent stumbling block to student comprehension of issues surrounding free will. Students tend to commit two main errors. First, they often confuse determinism with the related but importantly different idea of fatalism. Second, students often do not adequately understand that mental states, such as desires or beliefs, can function as deterministic causes. This paper outlines a straightforward in-class exercise modeled after John Horton Conway’s “Gam…Read more
  •  365
    The Oxford handbook of Spinoza (review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (3): 652-654. 2019.
    Volume 27, Issue 3, May 2019, Page 652-654.
  •  844
    Spinoza and the problem of other substances
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (4): 481-507. 2019.
    ABSTRACTMost of Spinoza’s arguments for God’s existence do not rely on any special feature of God, but instead on merely general features of substance. This raises the following worry: those arguments prove the existence of non-divine substances just as much as they prove God’s existence, and yet there is not enough room in Spinoza’s system for all these substances. I argue that Spinoza attempts to solve this problem by using a principle of plenitude to rule out the existence of other substances…Read more
  •  109
    Reply to Yenter: Spinoza, Number, and Diversity
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (2): 365-374. 2016.
    Clarke attacks Spinoza's monism on the grounds that it cannot explain how a multiplicity of things follows from one substance, God. This article argues that Clarke assumes that Spinoza's God is countable. It then sketches a way in which multiplicity can follow from God's uncountable nature.
  •  145
    Spinoza and the Feeling of Freedom
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 94 (4): 1-15. 2016.
    ABSTRACTWe seem to have a direct experience of our freedom when we act. Many philosophers take this feeling of freedom as evidence that we possess libertarian free will. Spinoza denies that we have free will of any sort, although he admits that we nonetheless feel free. Commentators often attribute to him what I call the ‘Negative Account’ of the feeling: it results from the fact that we are conscious of our actions but ignorant of their causes. I argue that the Negative Account is flawed. The f…Read more
  •  2371
    The Nozick Game
    Teaching Philosophy 40 (1): 1-10. 2017.
    In this article I introduce a simple classroom exercise intended to help students better understand Robert Nozick’s famous Wilt Chamberlain thought experiment. I outline the setup and rules of the Basic Version of the Game and explain its primary pedagogical benefits. I then offer several more sophisticated versions of the Game which can help to illustrate the difference between Nozick’s libertarianism and luck egalitarianism.
  •  98
    Cartesian Modes and The Simplicity of Mind
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 96 (1): 54-76. 2014.
    Malebranche argues that we lack a clear idea of the mind because we cannot, even in principle, derive all the possible modes of mind solely from the idea of thought. But we can, in principle, derive all the possible modes of body from the idea of extension. Therefore, there is epistemic asymmetry between our ideas of mind and body. I offer a defense of Descartes whereby he can assert that we have a clear idea of mind despite this asymmetry. I argue that he can do this by distinguishing the simpl…Read more