Annandale-on-Hudson, New York, United States of America
Areas of Interest
Philosophy of Mind
  •  312
    On philosophy as therapy: Wittgenstein, Cavell, and autobiographical writing
    Philosophy and Literature 27 (1): 196-210. 2003.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 27.1 (2003) 196-210 [Access article in PDF] On Philosophy as Therapy:Wittgenstein, Cavell, and Autobiographical Writing Garry Hagberg IN HIS LATER PHILOSOPHICAL WRITINGS Wittgenstein was exquisitely sensitive to the misleading implications housed within the formulations of philosophical questions. The question with which he opened the Blue Book, "What is the meaning of a word?," the question "What is thinkin…Read more
  •  251
    Leporello's question
    Philosophy and Literature 29 (1): 180-199. 2005.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Leporello's QuestionGarry L. HagbergOne finds in the later philosophical writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein an articulation of the distinctive attitude we bring to the perception of human beings. This attitude, called by Wittgenstein "Eine Einstellung zur Seele," an attitude towards a soul, is irreducible—it cannot be analyzed into any more basic constituent parts—and it is the precondition for our sympathetic and imaginative understand…Read more
  •  172
    What, after all, is a work of art?
    British Journal of Aesthetics 42 (2): 206-209. 2002.
  •  132
    On Representing Jazz: An Art Form in Need of Understanding
    Philosophy and Literature 26 (1): 188-198. 2002.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 26.1 (2002) 188-198 [Access article in PDF] Symposium: On Ken Burns's "Jazz" On Representing Jazz: An Art Form in Need of Understanding Garry L. Hagberg ALTHOUGH IT WENT ON in smaller numbers in earlier decades, the fact that there were legions of expatriate jazz musicians fleeing to a far more appreciative Europe in the 1960s and 1970s shows how important a cultural event Ken Burns's documentary on the firs…Read more
  •  89
    In 1931, in the remarks collected as Culture and Value, Wittgenstein writes: ‘A thinker is very much like a draughtsman whose aim it is to represent all the interrelations between things.’ At a glance it is clear that this analogy might contribute significantly to a full description of the autobiographical thinker as well. And this conjunction of relations between things and the work of the draughtsman immediately and strongly suggests that the grasping of relations is in a sense visual, or that…Read more
  •  86
    A Companion to the Philosophy of Literature (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2007.
    This monumental collection of new and recent essays from an international team of eminent scholars represents the best contemporary critical thinking relating to both literary and philosophical studies of literature. Helpfully groups essays into the field's main sub-categories, among them ‘Relations Between Philosophy and Literature’, ‘Emotional Engagement and the Experience of Reading’, ‘Literature and the Moral Life’, and ‘Literary Language’ Offers a combination of analytical precision and lit…Read more
  •  83
    The voluminous writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein contain some of the most profound reflections of recent times on the nature of the human subject and self-understanding - the human condition, philosophically speaking. Describing Ourselves mines those extensive writings for a conception of the self that stands in striking contrast to its predecessors as well as its more recent alternatives. More specifically, the book offers a detailed discussion of Wittgenstein's later writings on language and min…Read more
  •  79
  •  74
    Wittgenstein underground
    Philosophy and Literature 28 (2): 379-392. 2004.
    : This paper argues that Dostoevsky's Notes from Underground makes a fundamental point that runs directly counter to the received popular image of the work; i.e. the understanding that Notes describes a consciousness reflecting on itself, hermetically sealed within its own Cartesian interior. In truth, a closer reading shows that the mind depicted therein is profoundly relational and situated in a particularized context, and that this discursive mind characterizes what Wittgenstein says about me…Read more
  •  74
    Art and the unsay able: Langer's tractarian aesthetics
    British Journal of Aesthetics 24 (4): 325-340. 1984.
  •  63
    Art as Language: Wittgenstein, Meaning, and Aesthetic Theory
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 54 (4): 388-389. 1995.
  •  60
    Aristotle's Mimesis and Abstract Art
    Philosophy 59 (229). 1984.
    Does non-representational art itself constitute a refutation of any theory of art based upon mimesis or imitation? Our intuitions regarding this question seem to support an affirmative answer: it appears impossible to account for abstract and non-representational art in terms of imitation, because, to put the problem simply, if nothing is copied in a work of art then there can be nothing essentially imitative about it. The very notion of abstract imitative art seems self-contradictory
  •  54
    Davidson, self-knowledge, and autobiographical writing
    Philosophy and Literature 26 (2): 354-368. 2002.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy and Literature 26.2 (2002) 354-368 [Access article in PDF] Davidson, Self-knowledge, and Autobiographical Writing Garry Hagberg AMONG THE NUMEROUS THINGS that make any autobiographical undertaking so interesting is the fact that there exists no one-to-one correlation between a person's belief, intention, preference, desire, hope, fear, expectation, and so forth (through a list including many of the diverse things philosoph…Read more
  •  52
    Jazz Improvisation : A Mimetic Art ?
    Revue Internationale de Philosophie 4 (4): 469-485. 2006.
  •  50
    Foreword: Improvisation in the arts
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 58 (2): 95-97. 2000.
  •  47
    Creation as translation
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 46 (2): 249-258. 1987.
  •  44
    Understanding happiness
    Mind 93 (372): 589-591. 1984.
  •  41
    Thinking of Others: On the Talent for Metaphor, by Ted Cohen (review)
    Mind 119 (476): 1145-1151. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  41
    On Rhythm
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 68 (3): 281-284. 2010.
  •  37
    Narrative and Self-Understanding (edited book)
    Palgrave. 2019.
    This exciting new edited collection bridges the gap between narrative and self-understanding. The problem of self-knowledge is of universal interest; the nature or character of its achievement has been one continuing thread in our philosophical tradition for millennia. Likewise the nature of storytelling, the assembly of individual parts of a potential story into a coherent narrative structure, has been central to the study of literature. But how do we gain knowledge from an artform that is by d…Read more
  •  37
    Wittgenstein, Music and the Philosophy of Culture
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 21 23-40. 2014.
    Wittgenstein’s scattered remarks on music, when brought together and then related to his similarly scattered remarks on culture, show a deep and abiding concern with music as a repository and conveyer of meaning in human life. Yet the conception of meaning at work in these remarks is not of a kind that is amenable to brief or concise articulation. This paper explores that conception, considering in turn the relational networks within which musical meaning emerges, what he calls a discernible “ki…Read more
  •  36
    Word and Object: Museums and the Matter of Meaning
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 79 261-293. 2016.
    We often think of works of art as possessors of meaning, and we think of museums as places where that meaning can be exhibited and encountered. But it is precisely at this first step of thinking about artistic meaning that we too easily import a conceptually entrenched model or picture of linguistic meaning that then constrains our appreciation of artistic meaning and what museum exhibitions actually do. That model of linguistic meaning is atomism: the notion that the single, self-contained word…Read more
  •  35
    Review of Ray Monk, How to Read Wittgenstein (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (228). 2007.
  •  32
    Wittgenstein's aesthetics
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2007.
  •  32
    Self-Expression
    British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (1): 107-109. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  31
    The Approach of a Lyricist
    Common Knowledge 20 (2): 214-222. 2014.
    As part of a Common Knowledge colloquium on “lyric philosophy,” this essay considers some of the connections between linguistic and nonlinguistic meaning, the connection between linguistic meaning and what Wittgenstein called aspect perception or imagination-enriched perception, issues in the analysis of meaning down to constituent parts and the problematic legacy of atomistic approaches to word-meaning, the inflection of experience across time and across context and the role of sensibility in b…Read more
  •  30
    Art Rethought: The Social Practices of Art
    British Journal of Aesthetics 57 (3): 331-334. 2017.
    © British Society of Aesthetics 2017. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the British Society of Aesthetics. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected] exists, according to Nicholas Wolterstorff in this deeply engaging and exemplary study, a Grand Narrative that runs through much of our thinking about art. That narrative, emerging from and solidified since the eighteenth century, is in essence that art is created for, and remains in museum…Read more
  •  30
    Kivy’s Mystery: Absolute Music and What the Formalist Can (or Could) Hear
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism. forthcoming.
    Peter Kivy has said that the power of purely instrumental music remains an unexplained wonder. With this larger question in mind, I will consider: the issues in musical aesthetics that led to what Kivy termed his enhanced formalism, his conception of expressive properties in music and how a distinction between having and understanding an emotion can help clarify this issues here, and, most importantly for Kivy’s larger mystery, the way that counterpoint, in an often unrecognized way, can present…Read more
  •  26
    Fictional Worlds and the Moral Imagination (edited book)
    Palgrave-Macmillan. 2021.
    This edited collection investigates the kinds of moral reflection we can undertake within the imaginative worlds of literature. In philosophical contexts of ethical inquiry we can too easily forget that literary experience can play an important role in the cultivation of our ethical sensibilities. Because our ethical lives are conducted in the real world, fictional representations of this world can appear removed from ethical contemplation. However, as this stimulating volume shows, the dichotom…Read more
  •  26
    Introduction: On the Ground of Ethical Criticism
    Philosophy and Literature 39 (1A). 2015.
    One can characterize the relation between philosophy and literature in a number of interestingly different ways: literature provides examples that put flesh on the bones of philosophical ideas; literature shows what philosophy says; literature serves philosophy by displaying the complexity of circumstance that philosophy may oversimplify; literature captures a kind of content that is not amenable to propositional encapsulation; literature offers a portal into an imaginative world and a special k…Read more