•  6
    Culpability and Moral Vice
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 1-12. forthcoming.
    This paper raises four queries about Simester’s defective engagement with reason account of culpability found in his Fundamentals of Criminal Law: (1) the characterisation of the account in terms of moral ‘vices’; (2) the basis for identifying a vice as a ‘moral’ vice; (3) what is involved in an agent manifesting ‘insufficient care and concern’ for the interests of others; and (4) whether the account is an account of culpability generally, or is instead an account of criminal culpability, i.e., …Read more
  •  6
    Coercion
    In Dennis Patterson (ed.), A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, Wiley‐blackwell. 2010.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Coercion Law References.
  • Methodology
    In John Tasioulas (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Law, Cambridge University Press. 2020.
  •  25
    Legal Reasoning for Hedgehogs
    Ratio Juris 30 (4): 507-521. 2017.
  •  13
    Everything in its right place
    Jurisprudence 9 (2): 353-360. 2018.
  •  10
    Coercion, Threats, and the Puzzle of Blackmail
    In A. P. Simester & A. T. H. Smith (eds.), Harm and Culpability, Oxford University Press. pp. 215-38. 1996.
    This paper discusses the puzzle of blackmail, i.e. the way in which the threat of an otherwise legally permissible action can in some cases constitute blackmail. It argues that the key to understanding blackmail is in terms of coercion and threats, and the effect such threats have on the validity of a victim’s consent. The nature of coercion and of coercive threats is considered in detail to support the thesis that threats are prima facie impermissible, though often justified all-things-consider…Read more
  •  134
    Persuasive Authority in the Law
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 17 (1): 16-35. 2010.
    This article discusses the nature of persuasive authorities in the common law, and argues that many of them are best understood in terms of their (being regarded) as having theoretical rather than practical authorities for the courts that cite them. The contrast between theoretical and practical authority is examined at length in order to support the view that the treatment of many persuasive authorities by courts is more consistent with this view. Finally, it is argued that if persuasive author…Read more
  •  173
    Do precedents create rules?
    Legal Theory 11 (1): 1-26. 2005.
    This article argues that legal precedents do not create rules, but rather create a special type of reason in favour of a decision in later cases. Precedents are often argued to be analogous to statutes in their law-creating function, but the common law practice of distinguishing is difficult to reconcile with orthodox accounts of the function of rules. Instead, a precedent amounts to a decision on the balance of reasons in the case before the precedent court, and later courts are required to dec…Read more
  •  82
    What is a Crime?
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 27 (4): 609-632. 2007.
    This article presents a philosophical account of the nature of crime. It argues that the criminal law contains both fault-based crimes and strict liability offences, and that these two represent different paradigms of liability. It goes on to argue that the gist of fault-based crimes lies in their being public wrongs, not (as is often thought) because they wrong the public, but because the public is responsible for punishing them, i.e. because they merit state punishment. What makes wrongs deser…Read more
  •  72
    Precedent
    Philosophy Compass 2 (5). 2007.
    Precedent is a central feature of legal practice, requiring courts to follow decisions reached in earlier cases, thereby transforming the decisions in individual cases into a source of law. This article examines two major questions associated with precedent: (a) how to characterise the way that precedent operates as a source of law; and (b) how to justify the requirement that courts follow earlier decisions regardless of the merits of those decisions. Precedents are often thought to create gener…Read more
  •  165
    Coercion and the nature of law
    Legal Theory 7 (1): 35-57. 2001.
    It is a commonplace that coercion forms part of the nature of law: Law is inherently coercive. But how well founded is this claim, and what would it mean for coercion to be part of the of law? This article suggests that the claim is grounded in our current conception of law. The main focus of the article, however, is upon two major lines of argument that attempt to establish a link between law and coercion: one based upon the laws normativity. It argues that the claim that law is necessarily coe…Read more