•  48
    Substance and Attribute (review)
    Philosophical Review 89 (2): 317-320. 1980.
  • Essence and accident
    Analysis 26 (6): 185. 1966.
  •  33
    Wiggins on identity
    Analysis 29 (5): 173-174. 1969.
  •  65
    Hedonism
    American Philosophical Quarterly 12 (3): 223-233. 1975.
  •  30
    In this book I try to defend a traditional kind of dualism in regard to ethical theory. The idea is that Conscience and Self-love offer distinct but rational and reasonable objectives in our decision-making. When they conflict, pure reason does not resolve the issue. With this picture in mind, I argue that a kind of Platonistic realism in regard to morality is (still) intellectually permissible – has not yet been defeated. That is to say, it is permissible to hold that we ought to do what is mo…Read more
  •  135
    Essence and Accident
    Analysis 26 (6): 77-81. 1966.
  •  83
    Shoemaker's arguments against Locke
    Philosophical Quarterly 19 (76): 263-265. 1969.
  •  52
    Defending continuants
    Noûs 4 (3): 279-283. 1970.
  •  255
    Rigid designation
    Journal of Philosophy 72 (13): 363-369. 1975.
    I have been told that for some twenty minutes after reading this paper Kripke believed I had shown that proper names could be non-rigid designators. (Then, apparently, he found a crucial error in the set-up.) I take great pride in this (alleged) fact.
  •  90
    Constitutivity and identity
    Noûs 5 (3): 313-319. 1971.
  •  43
    Persons and predicability
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 46 (2). 1968.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  476
    In the first two chapters of the Monologion Anselm shows, or tries to show that “Of all the things that exist, there is one that is the best, greatest and supreme.” In this paper I examine his argument.
  •  76
    Sources of Essence
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 11 (1): 379-389. 1986.
    Almost everyone believes in modality de dicto. Necessarily, puppies are young dogs. The necessity here derives from the meaning of “puppy.” The term means young dog. Essentialism is belief in a more exotic sort of modality, one that does not derive from meaning in this direct and simple way. In the first two sections of this paper, I consider indexical and nonindexical kind terms and the sort of modality applicable to each. In the last section, I consider individuals and proper names.
  •  206
    Some Ontological Arguments
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (1): 18-32. 1993.
    This was an attempt to show what is wrong with Anselm’s ‘Ontological Argument’ for the existence of God. My present view is that Peter Millican has given us a similar, but much better line of attack in his “The One Fatal Flaw….” Paper.
  •  107
    Theseus' Clothes-Pin
    Analysis 44 (2). 1984.
  •  28
    Cook's reductionis
    Philosophia 17 (4): 509-515. 1987.
  •  319
    If God necessarily exists this has some interesting consequences. In this little note I mention some of these.
  •  23
    Divine Intervention and the Origin of Life
    Faith and Philosophy 10 (2): 170-180. 1993.
  •  276
    Here are a few remarks in regard to the first section of Alison Hills’s The Beloved Self. The topic is various forms of ‘Egoism.’ These are taken to be theories of practical reason – alternative answers to the question ‘what have I reason to do?’
  •  30206
    Roughly speaking, Augustine claims that ‘Immutable Truth’ is superior to the human mind and, consequently a legitimate candidate for the role of God. Clearly there is such a thing as Immutable Truth. So either that is God, or there is something superior to Immutable Truth, and that superior thing is God. I spell out this argument, and offer some objections to it.
  •  359
    Very few (if any) people believe that the world was created, and is maintained, by a thoroughly contemptible and malicious being. Do we have good reason for our disbelief? In the first part of this paper I offer an argument for the non-existence of such a being. According to this argument there is just too much good - too may good things - in the world for the ‘malicious being’ theory to be plausible. In the second part of the paper I briefly consider the applicability of similar arguments to …Read more
  •  47
    Cartesian Semantics
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 63-70. 1987.
    Descartes thought he could suppose he was the victim of massive deception in regard to the external world. In fact he undertakes the supposing of it.I will … suppose that … a certain evil spirit, not less clever and deceitful than powerful, has bent all his efforts to deceiving me. I will think that the sky, the air, the earth, colors, shapes, sounds, and all other external things are nothing but illusions and dreams that he has used to trick my credulity. I will regard myself as having no hands…Read more
  • Philo, a Jewish philosopher, is interesting for various reasons. For one thing, he was a contemporary of Jesus who was deeply interested in all things related to religion but apparently never heard of Jesus. For another his view of God presumably shows one (radical, but possible) set of ideas about God available at that time.
  •  115
    Indeterminate people
    Analysis 45 (3): 141-145. 1985.
    Here is the paper that was attacked by George Rea in his “How many minds…?” paper. Has this issue been resolved? Can there be entities such that there is no definite answer to the question “Are there 13 minds at work here, or 14?”
  •  56
    Three Kinds of Classses
    American Philosophical Quarterly 3 (1): 77-188. 1966.
    This is a boiled down version of my doctoral dissertation. Ryle wouldn’t publish it, claiming that it is like ‘a well sharpened pencil that no one will ever use.’ I guess he turned out to be right. Nevertheless I think it was, and is, a good paper.