•  312
    Actualism, Possibilism, and Beyond
    Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics. 2012.
    How is what an agent ought to do related to what an agent ought to prefer that she does? More precisely, suppose we know what an agent’s preference ordering ought to be over the prospects of performing the various courses of action open to her. Can we infer from this information how she ought to act, and if so, how can we infer it? One view (which, for convenience, I will call ‘actualism’) is that an agent ought to  just in case she ought to prefer the prospect of her -ing to the prospect of h…Read more
  •  289
    Rejecting ethical deflationism
    Ethics 116 (4): 742-768. 2006.
    One of the perennial challenges of ethical theory has been to provide an answer to a number of views that appear to undermine the importance of ethical questions. We may refer to such views collectively as “deflationary ethical theories.” These include theories, such as nihilism, according to which no action is better than any other, as well as relativistic theories according to which no ethical theory is better than any other. In this article I present a new response to such deflationary ethica…Read more
  •  280
    Should Kantians be consequentialists?
    Ratio 22 (1): 126-135. 2009.
    Parfit argues that a form of rule consequentialism can be derived from the most plausible formulation of the fundamental principle of Kantian ethics. And so he concludes that Kantians should be consequentialists. I argue that we have good reason to reject two of the auxiliary premises that figure in Parfit's derivation of rule consequentialism from Kantianism. 1.
  •  222
    What theory should we accept from the practical point of view, or accept as a basis for guiding our actions, if we don’t know which theory is true, and if there are too many plausible alternative theories for us to take them all into consideration? This question is the theme of the first three parts of this dissertation. I argue that the problem of theory acceptance, so understood, is a problem of practical rationality, and hence that the appropriate grounds for theory acceptance are practical c…Read more
  •  186
    The Irreducibility of Personal Obligation
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (3). 2010.
    It is argued that claims about personal obligation (of the form "s ought to 0") cannot be reduced to claims about impersonal obligation (of the form "it ought to be the case that p"). The most common attempts at such a reduction are shown to have unacceptable implications in cases involving a plurality of agents. It is then argued that similar problems will face any attempt to reduce personal obligation to impersonal obligation
  •  120
    Divided we fall
    Philosophical Perspectives 28 (1): 222-262. 2014.
  •  119
    Self-interest is widely regarded as an important, if not as the only, source of reasons for action, and hence it is widely held that one can rationally give special weight to one’s self-interest in deciding how to act. In what follows, I will argue against this view. I will do so by following the lead of Derek Parfit, and considering cases in which personal identity appears to break down. My argument will differ from Parfit’s, however, in that it will have a stronger conclusion, it will involve …Read more
  •  89
    How are claims about what people ought to do related to claims about what ought to be the case? That is, how are claims about of personal obligation, of the form s ought to ?, related to claims about impersonal obligation, of the form it ought to be the case that p? Many philosophers have held that the former type of claim can be reduced to the latter. In particular, they have held a view known as the Meinong-Chisholm Thesis, which, on its simplest formulation, can be stated thus: MCT: s ought t…Read more
  •  87
    Rationality, Normativity, and-1 Commitment
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 7 138. 2012.
  •  79
    It is generally thought that there are certain persons to whose welfare we should give special weight. It is commonly held, for example, that we should give special weight to our own welfare. On the strongest version of this view, we should always give overriding weight to our own welfare, and so, in considering any set of alternatives, we should always prefer the one in which we fare best. Many people would reject this strong view, for two reasons. First, many people would hold that impersonal …Read more
  •  73
    Knowledge Dethroned
    Analytic Philosophy 58 (4): 283-296. 2017.
  •  55
    Elijah delmedigo
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  52
    John Broome, Weighing Lives (review)
    Philosophical Review 116 (4): 663-666. 2007.
  •  40
    Weighing Lives
    Philosophical Review 116 (4): 663-666. 2007.
  •  30
    A Qualified Defence of Expected Value Maximization
    Analysis 81 (4): 731-746. 2022.
  •  11
    Knowledge, Safety, and Meta‐Epistemic Belief
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (3): 550-554. 2018.
    This article raises problems both for the view that safe belief is necessary for knowledge and for the view that it is sufficient. Focusing on ‘meta‐epistemic beliefs,’ or beliefs about the epistemic status of one's own beliefs, it is shown that the necessity claim has counterintuitive implications and that the sufficiency claim implies a contradiction. It is then shown that meta‐epistemic beliefs raise similar problems for a wide range of accounts of knowledge, and hence that they provide a pow…Read more
  •  5
    Should Kantians Be Consequentialists?
    In Jussi Suikkanen & John Cottingham (eds.), Essays on Derek Parfit's On what matters, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  • Moral Skepticism
    with Matt Lutz
    In Tristram Colin McPherson & David Plunkett (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics, Routledge. pp. 484-498. 2017.