•  8
    First published in 2005. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company
  •  24
    The Nature of all Being (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (4): 643-664. 1994.
  •  17
    Fire in the Belly: Aristotelian Elements, Organisms, and Chemical Compounds
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76 (3-4): 370-404. 2017.
  •  24
    II. An unfavorable review oflanguage, sense and nonsense∗
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 28 (1-4): 467-482. 1985.
  •  34
    Was wittgenstein a psychologist? (I)
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 7 (1-4): 374-378. 1964.
    Certain remarks in the Tractatus, taken together with a passage in a letter Wittgenstein wrote to Russell, suggest that at one time Wittgenstein inclined toward a psychologistic theory of language. But textual considerations with regard to the former and a special interpretation of the latter allow us to interpret these statements in a way that is consistent with Wittgenstein's later views
  •  30
    Wittgenstein (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 12 (3): 344-345. 1989.
  •  43
    Recent Wittgensteiniana (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 4 (1): 67-74. 1981.
  •  24
    Review (review)
    Synthese 55 (3): 373-388. 1983.
  •  60
    Agony in the Schools
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (1): 1-21. 1981.
    Functionalist identity theorists argue that if physical states of the central nervous system have the same function as pain, pains should be identified with those physical states. Many objections have been raised against this position. My aim in this paper is to defend it against opponents who argue that it leads to an absurd result: the ascription of pains to things which cannot reasonably be thought to be capable of suffering, or of having any conscious states. In doing this, I will outline a …Read more
  •  89
    Metaphors as theory fragments
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 37 (2): 177-188. 1978.
  •  29
    Human Knowledge (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 11 (2): 183-185. 1988.
  •  57
    Freedom and happiness in mill's defence of liberty
    with Daniel M. Farrell
    Philosophical Quarterly 28 (113): 325-338. 1978.
  •  31
    Aristotle’s Great Clock
    Philosophy Research Archives 12 387-448. 1986.
    This paper offers a detailed account of arguments in De Caelo I by which Aristotle tried to demonstrate the necessity of the perpetual existence and the perpetual rotation of the cosmos. On our interpretation, Aristotle’s arguments are naturalistic. Instead of being based (as many have thought) on rules of logic and language, they depend, we argue, on natural science theories about abilities (δυνάμεις), e.g., to move and to change, which things have by nature and about the conditions under which…Read more
  •  21
    Aristotle’s Great Clock
    Philosophy Research Archives 12 387-448. 1986.
    This paper offers a detailed account of arguments in De Caelo I by which Aristotle tried to demonstrate the necessity of the perpetual existence and the perpetual rotation of the cosmos. On our interpretation, Aristotle’s arguments are naturalistic. Instead of being based (as many have thought) on rules of logic and language, they depend, we argue, on natural science theories about abilities (δυνάμεις), e.g., to move and to change, which things have by nature and about the conditions under which…Read more
  •  3
    Aristotle's Forbidden Sweets
    with J. M. E. Moravcsik
    University of California Press]. 1982.
  •  258
    Regularities and causality; generalizations and causal explanations
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36 (2): 397-420. 2005.
    Machamer, Darden, and Craver argue that causal explanations explain effects by describing the operations of the mechanisms which produce them. One of this paper’s aims is to take advantage of neglected resources of Mechanism to rethink the traditional idea that actual or counterfactual natural regularities are essential to the distinction between causal and non-causal co-occurrences, and that generalizations describing natural regularities are essential components of causal explanations. I think…Read more
  •  256
    Causally productive activities
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 39 (1): 112-123. 2008.
    This paper suggests and discusses an answer to the following question: What distinguishes causal from non-causal or coincidental co-occurrences? The answer derives from Elizabeth Anscombe’s idea that causality is a highly abstract concept whose meaning derives from our understanding of specific causally productive activities, and from her rejection of the assumption that causality can be informatively understood in terms of actual or counterfactual regularities.Keywords: Elizabeth Anscombe; Caus…Read more
  •  40
    Wittgenstein’s Tractatus (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 5 (4): 325-326. 1982.
  •  73
    Familiar versions of empiricism overemphasize and misconstrue the importance of perceptual experience. I discuss their main shortcomings and sketch an alternative framework for thinking about how human sensory systems contribute to scientific knowledge.
  •  37
  •  76
    Mechanistic Information and Causal Continuity
    In Phyllis McKay Illari, Federica Russo & Jon Williamson (eds.), Causality in the Sciences, Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Some biological processes move from step to step in a way that cannot be completely understood solely in terms of causes and correlations. This paper develops a notion of mechanistic information that can be used to explain the continuities of such processes. We compare them to processes that do not involve information. We compare our conception of mechanistic information to some familiar notions including Crick’s idea of genetic information, Shannon-Weaver information, and Millikan’s biosemantic…Read more
  •  32
    The New Mechanical Philosophy
    Metascience 17 (1): 33-41. 2008.
  •  51
    Noise in the World
    Philosophy of Science 77 (5): 778-791. 2010.
    This essay uses Györgi Buzsáki's use of EEG data to draw conclusions about brain function as an example to show that investigators sometimes draw conclusions from noisy data by analyzing the noise rather than by extracting a signal from it. The example makes vivid some important differences between McAllister's, Woodward's, and my ideas about how data are interpreted.
  •  51
    Occasion-Sensitivity – Charles Travis
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (242): 196-201. 2011.
  •  246
    Theory and observation in science
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2009.
    Scientists obtain a great deal of the evidence they use by observingnatural and experimentally generated objects and effects. Much of thestandard philosophical literature on this subject comes from20th century logical positivists and empiricists, theirfollowers, and critics who embraced their issues and accepted some oftheir assumptions even as they objected to specific views. Theirdiscussions of observational evidence tend to focus on epistemologicalquestions about its role in theory testing. T…Read more
  •  48
    This paper compares the relative merits of two alternatives to traditional accounts of causal explanation: Jim Woodward's counterfactual invariance account, and the Mechanistic account of Machamer, Darden, and Craver. Mechanism wins (a) because we have good causal explanations for chaotic effects whose production does not exhibit the counterfactual regularities Woodward requires, and (b)because arguments suggested by Belnap's and Green's discussion of prediction (in'Facing the Future' chpt 6)sho…Read more