•  292
    I argue that these inconsistencies in wording and practice reflect the existence of two distinct Aristotelian views of inquiry, one peculiar to the Posterior Analytics and the other put forward in the Physics and practiced in the Physics and in other treatises. Although the two views overlap to some degree (e.g. both regard a rudimentary understanding of the subject as an essential first stage), the view of the syllogism as the workhorse of scientific investigation and the related view of inquir…Read more
  •  15
    The emergence of philosophical interest in cognition
    Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 12 1-34. 1994.
    On some accounts, early reflection on the nature of human cognition focused on its physical or physiological causes (as, for example, when in fragment 105 Empedocles identifies thought with blood). On other accounts, there was an identifiable process of semantic development in which a number of perception-oriented terms for knowing (e.g. gignôskô, oida, noeô, and suniêmi) took on a more intellectual orientation. Although some find evidence of this transition in the poems of Solon and Archilochus…Read more
  •  139
    Western philosophy begins with Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes. Or so we are told by Aristotle and many members of the later doxographical tradition. But a good case can be made that several centuries before the Milesian thinkers began their investigations, the poets of archaic Greece reflected on the limits of human intelligence and concluded that no mortal being could know the full and certain truth. Homer belittled the mental capacities of ‘creatures of a day’ and a series of poets of the…Read more
  •  5
    1 Parmenidean Elenchos
    In Scott Gary Alan (ed.), Does Socrates Have a Method?: Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato's Dialogues and Beyond, Pennsylvania State University Press. pp. 19-35. 2002.
  •  40
    The humanizing of knowledge in presocratic thought
    In Patricia Curd & Daniel W. Graham (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Presocratic Philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    This article explores Presocratic epistemology, arguing that divine revelation is replaced as a warrant for knowledge with naturalistic accounts of how and what we humans can know; thus replacing earlier Greek pessimism about knowledge with a more optimistic outlook that allows for human discovery of the truth. A review of the relevant fragments and testimonia shows that Xenophanes, Alcmaeon, Heraclitus, and Parmenides—even Pythagoras and Empedocles—all moved some distance away from the older “g…Read more
  •  63
    Socrates' disavowal of knowledge
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 25 (2): 275-288. 1987.
  •  18
    Perceiving and Knowing in the Iliad and Odyssey
    Phronesis 26 (1): 2-24. 1981.
  •  22
    Borges's Love Affair with Heraclitus
    Philosophy and Literature 41 (1A): 303-314. 2017.
    In an early poem, "Year's End", Jorge Luis Borges takes the turning of the year as an occasion to consider how "something in us" endures, despite the fact that we are products of "infinite random possibilities" and "droplets in the stream of Heraclitus": It is not the emblematic detail of replacing a two with a three, nor that barren metaphor that brings together a time that dies and another coming up nor yet the rounding out of some astronomical process that stuns and undermines the altiplano1 …Read more
  •  31
    Aristotle's Theory of the Unity of Science (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (2): 290-292. 2001.
    Malcolm Wilson begins his account of Aristotle’s philosophy of science by identifying a difficulty inherent in Aristotle’s general approach to understanding the nature of scientific thought: if we assume, with Aristotle, that the premises of a scientific demonstration must contain only terms predicable of a subject essentially (or per se) and ‘as such’ (or qua a particular kind of being), we risk being committed to a view of the sciences as a set of narrowly focused and unrelated areas of inquir…Read more
  •  11
    Aristotle (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 12 (1): 79-82. 1989.
  •  7
    MacNeice the Heraclitean
    Philosophy and Literature 45 (2): 315-328. 2021.
    ARRAY
  •  65
    Just as in battle
    Ancient Philosophy 30 (1): 95-105. 2010.
  •  23
    Hume's analysis of "cause" and the 'two-definitions' dispute
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 11 (3): 387-392. 1973.
  •  44
    An Interdisciplinary Course on Classical Athens
    Teaching Philosophy 5 (3): 203-210. 1982.
  •  15
    Τὰ Πολλὰ Ἥσσω Νοῦ
    Ancient Philosophy 42 (1): 1-9. 2022.
    Diogenes Laertius reports that Xenophanes of Colophon said that τὰ πολλὰ ἥσσω νοῦ εἶναι— on one defensible translation: that ‘many things are weaker than mind.’ The remark has been interpreted in various ways, none of them entirely convincing. However, a review of the relevant fragments and ancient testimonia will provide the basis for a credible interpretation. Ultimately, it will emerge that the remark reflects Xenophanes’ understanding of the relationship between the divine mind and the cosmo…Read more
  •  31
    Aristotle (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 12 (1): 79-82. 1989.
  • A systematic Xenophanes?
    In Joe McCoy & Charles H. Kahn (eds.), Early Greek philosophy: the Presocratics and the emergence of reason, Catholic University of America Press. 2013.
  •  225
    Knowledge and Presence in Early Greek Poetry and Philosophy
    In ‘Knowledge’ in Archaic Greece: What Counted as ‘knowledge’ Before there was a Discipline called Philosophy, Center For Hellenic Studies. forthcoming.
    Philosophical reflection on the conditions of knowledge did not begin in a cultural vacuum. Several centuries before the Ionian thinkers began their investigations, the Homeric bards had identified various factors that militate against a secure grasp of the truth. In the words of the ‘second invocation of the Muses’ in Iliad II: “you, goddesses, are present and know all things, whereas we mortals hear only a rumor and know nothing.” Similarly Archilochus: “Of such a sort, Glaucus, son of Leptine…Read more
  •  230
  •  205
    This study forms a part of a larger investigation of the influence of the philosophy of Heraclitus of Ephesus on modern poetry. T. S. Eliot, to mention the best known of the many poets inspired by Heraclitus, selected two Heraclitus fragments (B 2 and B 60) as epigraphs for his “Burnt Norton”, the first of his Four Quartets. Eliot explained that he was drawn to the fragments because of their ‘ambiguity’ and ‘extraordinary poetic suggestiveness’. Similarly, in ‘This Solitude of Cataracts’, Walla…Read more