•  627
    In De Anima 2.4, Aristotle claims that nutritive soul encompasses two distinct biological functions: nutrition and reproduction. We challenge a pervasive interpretation which posits ‘nutrients’ as the correlative object of the nutritive capacity. Instead, the shared object of nutrition and reproduction is that which is nourished and reproduced: the ensouled body, qua ensouled. Both functions aim at preserving this object, and thus at preserving the form, life, and being of the individual organis…Read more
  •  294
    Darwin was a teleologist
    Biology and Philosophy 8 (4): 409-421. 1993.
    It is often claimed that one of Darwin''s chief accomplishments was to provide biology with a non-teleological explanation of adaptation. A number of Darwin''s closest associates, however, and Darwin himself, did not see it that way. In order to assess whether Darwin''s version of evolutionary theory does or does not employ teleological explanation, two of his botanical studies are examined. The result of this examination is that Darwin sees selection explanations of adaptations as teleological …Read more
  •  214
    Plato's Unnatural Teleology
    In Dominic J. O'Meara (ed.), Platonic Investigations, Catholic University of Amer Press. pp. 195-218. 1985.
  •  187
    Health as an objective value
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 20 (5): 499-511. 1995.
    Variants on two approaches to the concept of health have dominated the philosophy of medicine, here referred to as ‘reductionist’ and ‘relativis’. These two approaches share the basic assumption that the concept of health cannot be both based on an empirical biological foundation and be evaluative, and thus adopt either the view that it is ‘objective’ or evaluative. It is here argued that there are a subset of value concepts that are formed in recognition of certain fundamental facts about livin…Read more
  •  165
    Teleology, chance, and Aristotle's theory of spontaneous generation
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 20 (3): 219-238. 1982.
  •  150
    Aristotle on Chance
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 66 (1): 52-60. 1984.
  •  138
    Aristotle on Norms of Inquiry
    Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 1 (1): 23-46. 2011.
    Where does Aristotle stand in the debate between rationalism and empiricism? The locus classicus on this question, Posterior Analytics II. 19, seems clearly empiricist. Yet many commentators have resisted this conclusion. Here, I review their arguments and conclude that they rest in part on expectations for this text that go unfulfilled. I argue that this is because his views about norms of empirical inquiry are in the rich methodological passages in his scientific treatises. In support of this …Read more
  •  107
    Aristotle on the Emergence of Material Complexity: Meteorology IV and Aristotle’s Biology
    Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (2): 272-305. 2014.
    In this article I defend an account of Meteorology IV as providing a material-level causal account of the emergence of uniform materials with a wide range of dispositional properties not found at the level of the four elements—the emergence of material complexity. I then demonstrate that this causal account is used in the Generation of Animals and Parts of Animals as part of the explanation of the generation of the uniform parts (tissues) and of their role in providing nonuniform parts (organs) …Read more
  •  100
    Aristotle on the unity and disunity of science
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (2). 2001.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  90
    The Place of Mankind in Aristotle’s Zoology
    Philosophical Topics 27 (1): 1-16. 1999.
    Historians of psychology often treat Aristotle’s De Anima as the first scientific treatment of their subject; and historians of biology do likewise with his zoological treatises. How are the investigations recorded in works such as the Parts of Animals and History of Animals connected to those in the De Anima? More specifically, given Aristotle’s views about man’s special and distinctive cognitive capacities, what does he think about man as an object of a distinctively zoological investigation? …Read more
  •  86
    Natural selection and the struggle for existence
    with Bradley E. Wilson
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (1): 65-80. 1994.
  •  84
    This essay outlines one aspect of a larger collaboration with John Beatty and Alan Love.2 The project’s focus is philosophical, but for reasons that will become clear momentarily, the method of approach is historical. All three of us share the conviction that philosophical issues concerning the foundations of the sciences are often illuminated by investigating their history. It is my hope that this paper both provides support for that thesis, and illustrates it. The focal philosophical issue can…Read more
  •  82
    Aristotle's biology
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Aristotle is properly recognized as the originator of the scientific study of life. This is true despite the fact that many earlier Greek natural philosophers occasionally speculated on the origins of living things and much of the Hippocratic medical corpus, which was written before or during Aristotle's lifetime, displays a serious interest in human anatomy, physiology and pathology. Even Plato has Timaeus devote a considerable part of his speech to the human body and its functions (and malfunc…Read more
  •  78
    Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle: Essays in Honor of Allan Gotthelf (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2010.
    This volume of essays explores major connected themes in Aristotle's metaphysics, philosophy of nature, and ethics, especially themes related to essence, definition, teleology, activity, potentiality, and the highest good. The volume is united by the belief that all aspects of Aristotle's work need to be studied together if any one of the areas of thought is to be fully understood. Many of the papers were contributions to a conference at the University of Pittsburgh entitled 'Being, Nature, and …Read more
  •  77
    Teleology by another name: A reply to Ghiselin (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 9 (4): 493-495. 1994.
  •  76
    Darwin’s Methodological Evolution
    Journal of the History of Biology 38 (1): 85-99. 2005.
    A necessary condition for having a revolution named after you is that you are an innovator in your field. I argue that if Charles Darwin meets this condition, it is as a philosopher and methodologist. In 1991, I made the case for Darwin's innovative use of "thought experiment" in the "Origin." Here I place this innovative practice in the context of Darwin's methodological commitments, trace its origins back into Darwin's notebooks, and pursue Darwin's suggestion that it owes its inspiration to C…Read more
  •  76
    The Causality of Finite Modes in Spinoza's "Ethics"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (3). 1976.
    A central difficulty in the way of understanding Spinoza's metaphysical system is that of reconciling two apparently contradictory theories of the causation of finite modes found in his Ethics. The easiest way to present the problem is to place these two accounts side by side.A. All things which follow from the absolute nature of any attribute of God must forever exist, and must be infinite; that is to say, through that attribute they are eternal and infinite. A thing which has been determined t…Read more
  •  75
    Philosophical Issues in Aristotle's Biology (edited book)
    with Allan Gotthelf
    Cambridge University Press. 1987.
    Aristotle's biological works - constituting over 25% of his surviving corpus and for centuries largely unstudied by philosophically oriented scholars - have been the subject of an increasing amount of attention of late. This collection brings together some of the best work that has been done in this area, with the aim of exhibiting the contribution that close study of these treatises can make to the understanding of Aristotle's philosophy. The book is divided into four parts, each with an introd…Read more
  •  50
    The complexity of Aristotle's study of animals
    In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle, Oup Usa. pp. 287. 2012.
    Aristotle is the first person in the history of science to see the study of nature as an articulated complex of interrelated, yet somewhat autonomous, investigations. Understanding why goes to the heart of what is philosophically distinctive about him. Why does Aristotle present the investigation of “the common cause of animal motion” as distinct and independent from a study of the causes of the different forms of animal locomotion, the announced project of De incessu animalium? This article exa…Read more
  •  50
    Darwinism
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
    Darwinism designates a distinctive form of evolutionary explanation for the history and diversity of life on earth. Its original formulation is provided in the first edition of On the Origin of Species in 1859. This entry first formulates ‘Darwin's Darwinism’ in terms of five philosophically distinctive themes: (i) probability and chance, (ii) the nature, power and scope of selection, (iii) adaptation and teleology, (iv) nominalism vs. essentialism about species and (v) the tempo and mode of evo…Read more
  •  46
    Aristotle's de generatione et corruptione
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 22 (4): 472-474. 1984.
  •  45
    Aristotelian Problems (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 14 (2): 53-77. 1994.