•  122
    What's wrong with Libertarianism (review)
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 11 (3): 407-467. 1997.
    Libertarian arguments about the empirical benefits of capitalism are, as yet, inadequate to convince anyone who lacks libertarian philosophical convictions. Yet “philosophical” libertarianism founders on internal contradictions that render it unfit to make libertarians out of anyone who does not have strong consequentialist reasons for libertarian belief. The joint failure of these two approaches to libertarianism explains why they are both present in orthodox libertarianism—they hide each other…Read more
  •  110
    Political Epistemology
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 26 (1-2). 2014.
    ABSTRACTNormative political epistemologists, such as epistemic democrats, study whether political decision makers can, in principle, be expected to know what they need to know if they are to make wise public policy. Empirical political epistemologists study the content and sources of real-world political actors' knowledge and interpretations of knowledge. In recent years, empirical political epistemologists have taken up the study of the ideas of political actors other than voters, such as burea…Read more
  •  103
    Popper, Weber, and Hayek: The epistemology and politics of ignorance
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 17 (1-2): 1-58. 2005.
    Karl Popper's methodology highlights our scientific ignorance: hence the need to institutionalize open‐mindedness through controlled experiments that may falsify our fallible theories about the world. In his endorsement of “piecemeal social engineering,” Popper assumes that the social‐democratic state and its citizens are capable of detecting social problems, and of assessing the results of policies aimed at solving them, through a process of experimentation analogous to that of natural science.…Read more
  •  83
    A Crisis of Politics, Not Economics: Complexity, Ignorance, and Policy Failure
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 21 (2-3): 127-183. 2009.
    ABSTRACT The financial crisis was caused by the complex, constantly growing web of regulations designed to constrain and redirect modern capitalism. This complexity made investors, bankers, and perhaps regulators themselves ignorant of regulations promulgated across decades and in different “fields” of regulation. These regulations interacted with each other to foster the issuance and securitization of subprime mortgages; their rating as AA or AAA; and previously their concentration on the balan…Read more
  •  71
    Ignorance as a starting point: From modest epistemology to realistic political theory
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 19 (1): 1-22. 2007.
    No abstract
  •  65
    Roundtable on Political Epistemology
    with Scott Althaus, Mark Bevir, Hélène Landemore, Rogers Smith, and Susan Stokes
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 26 (1-2): 1-32. 2014.
    On August 30, 2013, the American Political Science Association sponsored a roundtable on political epistemology as part of its annual meetings. Co-chairing the roundtable were Jeffrey Friedman, Department of Government, University of Texas at Austin; and Hélène Landemore, Department of Political Science, Yale University. The other participants were Scott Althaus, Department of Political Science, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign; Mark Bevir, Department of Political Science, University o…Read more
  •  64
    Hayek's Two Epistemologies and the Paradoxes of His Thought
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 25 (3-4): 277-304. 2013.
    Hayek developed two contradictory epistemologies. The epistemology for which he is famous attributed dispersed knowledge to economic actors and credited the price system for aggregating and communicating this knowledge. The other epistemology attributed to human and non-human organisms alike the error-prone interpretation of stimuli, which could never truly be said to be “knowledge.” Several of the paradoxes of Hayek's economic and political thought that are explored in this symposium can be exp…Read more
  •  60
    The politics of communitarianism
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 8 (2): 297-340. 1994.
    Taylor, Sandel, Walzer, and MacIntyre waver between granting the community authority over the individual and limiting this authority so severely that communitarianism becomes a dead letter. The reason for this vacillation can be found in the aspiration of each theorist to base liberal values‐equality and liberty—on particularism. Communitarians compound liberal formalism by adding to the liberal goal, individual autonomy, the equally abstract aim of grounding autonomy in a communally shared iden…Read more
  •  54
    “Search” vs. “browse”: A theory of error grounded in radical (not rational) ignorance
    with Anthony J. Evans
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 23 (1-2): 73-104. 2011.
    Economists tend to view ignorance as ?rational,? neglecting the possibility that ignorance is unintentional. This oversight is reflected in economists? model of ?information search,? which can be fruitfully contrasted with ?information browsing.? Information searches are designed to discover unknown knowns, whose value is calculable ex ante, such that this value justifies the cost of the search. In this model of human information acquisition, there is no primal or ?radical? ignorance that might …Read more
  •  52
    Roundtable 1: Public ignorance: Rational, irrational, or inevitable?
    with Scott Althaus, Bryan Caplan, Ilya Somin, and Nassim Nicholas Taleb
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (4): 423-444. 2008.
  •  52
    The Irrelevance of Economic Theory to Understanding Economic Ignorance
    with Stephen Earl Bennett
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (3): 195-258. 2008.
    Bryan Caplan’s The Myth of the Rational Voter treats several immensely important and understudied topics—public ignorance of economics, political ideology, and their connection to policy error—from an orthodox economic perspective whose applicability to these topics is overwhelmingly disproven by the available evidence. Moreover, Caplan adds to the traditional and largely irrelevant orthodox economic notion of rational public ignorance the claim that when voters favor counterproductive economic …Read more
  •  52
    Roundtable 4: Political dogmatism
    with Scott Althaus, David Barash, George E. Marcus, and Charles S. Taber
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (4): 481-498. 2008.
  •  51
    This volume brings Cassirer s work into the arena of contemporary debates both within and outside of philosophy. All articles offer a fresh and contemporary look at one of the most prolific and important philosophers of the 20th century. The papers are authored by a wide array of scholars working in different areas, such as epistemology, philosophy of culture, sociology, psychopathology, philosophy of science and aesthetics."
  •  49
    Roundtable 3: Political ignorance, empirical realities
    with Samuel DeCanio, David R. Mayhew, Michael H. Murakami, and Nick Weller
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (4): 463-480. 2008.
  •  42
    The bias issue
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 17 (3-4): 221-236. 2005.
    No abstract
  •  41
    “The Nature of Belief Systems” sets forth a Hobson's choice between rule by the politically ignorant masses and rule by the ideologically constrained—which is to say, the doctrinaire—elites. On the one hand, lacking comprehensive cognitive structures, such as ideological “belief systems,” with which to understand politics, most people learn distressingly little about it. On the other hand, a spiral of conviction seems to make it difficult for the highly informed few to see any aspects of politic…Read more
  •  41
    Pluralism or relativism?
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 11 (4): 469-479. 1997.
  •  39
    Taking ignorance seriously: Rejoinder to critics
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 18 (4): 467-532. 2006.
    In “Popper, Weber, and Hayek,” I claimed that the economic and political world governed by social democracy is too complex to offer hope for rational social‐democratic policy making. I extrapolated this conclusion from the claim, made by Austrian‐school economists in the 1920s and 30s, that central economic planning would face insurmountable “knowledge problems.” Israel Kirzner's Reply indicates the need to keep the Austrians’ cognitivist argument conceptually distinct from more familiar incenti…Read more
  •  37
    After libertarianism: Rejoinder to Narveson, McCloskey, Flew, and Machan
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 6 (1): 113-152. 1992.
    Postlibertarianism means abandoning defenses of the intrinsic justice of laissez?faire capitalism, the better to investigate whether the systemic consequences of interfering with capitalism are severe enough to justify laissez?faire. Any sound case for laissez?faire is likely to build on postlibertarian research, for the conviction that laissez?faire is intrinsically just rests upon unsound philosophical assumptions. Conversely, these assumptions, if sound, would make empirical studies of capita…Read more
  •  37
    Hayek's political philosophy and his economics
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 11 (1): 1-10. 1997.
    No abstract
  •  35
    Freedom has no intrinsic value: Liberalism and voluntarism
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 25 (1): 38-85. 2013.
    Deontological (as opposed to consequentialist) liberals treat freedom of action as an end in itself, not a means to other ends. Yet logically, when one makes a deliberate choice, one treats freedom of action as if it were not an end in itself, for one uses this freedom as a means to the ends one hopes to achieve through one's action. The tension between deontology and the logic of choice is reflected in the paradoxical nature of the ?right to do wrong?; and in Rawls's unsuccessful attempts to ju…Read more
  •  35
    Roundtable 2: Ignorance and error
    with Scott Althaus, John Bullock, Arthur Lupia, and Paul Quirk
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 20 (4): 445-461. 2008.
  •  35
    The new consensus: I. The Fukuyama thesis
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 3 (3-4): 373-410. 1989.
    Fukuyama's argument that we have recently reached ?The End of History?; is defended against writers who fail to appreciate the Hegelian meaning of Fukuyama's ?Endism,?; but is criticized for using simplistic dichotomies that evade the economic and ideological convergence of East and West. Against Fukuyama, the economic critique of socialism, revisionist scholarship on early Soviet economic history, and the history of the libertarian ideas of Rousseau, Kant, Hegel and Marx are deployed to show th…Read more
  •  34
    Economic approaches to politics
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 9 (1-2): 1-24. 1995.
    The debate over Green and Shapiro's Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory sustains their contention that rational choice theory has not produced novel, empirically sustainable findings about politics?if one accepts their definition of empirically sustainable findings. Green and Shapiro show that rational choice research often resembles the empirically vacuous practices in which economists engage under the aegis of instrumentalism. Yet Green and Shapiro's insistence that theoretical constructs sh…Read more
  •  34
    Motivated Skepticism or Inevitable Conviction? Dogmatism and the Study of Politics
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 24 (2): 131-155. 2012.
    Taber and Lodge's 2006 paper provides powerful evidence that one's prior beliefs shape one's reception of new evidence in a manner that can best be described as “inadvertently dogmatic.” This is especially true for people who are well informed, which dovetails with findings going back to Converse (1964) showing political beliefs to be ideologically constrained (rigid) among the relatively well informed. What may explain the coincidence of dogmatism and knowledgeability is the very process of lea…Read more
  •  34
    Postmodernism vs. Postlibertarianism
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 5 (2): 145-158. 1991.
    “Postmodernism” denotes efforts to replace foundationalist philosophy with contextu‐alist, immanentist forms of reason. “Postlibertarianism” denotes efforts to transcend contemporary minimal statism, questioning both its “libertarian” moral superstructure and its underlying consequentialist claims and seeking to determine whether the latter can be generalized in a way that displaces the former. Efforts to reach minimal‐statist conclusions by postmodern means seem bound to aggravate the problem t…Read more
  •  33
    Public ignorance and democratic theory
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 12 (4): 397-411. 1998.
    No abstract
  •  32
    After democracy, bureaucracy? Rejoinder to Ciepley
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 14 (1): 113-137. 2000.
    In a certain sense, voluntary communities and market relationships are relatively less coercive than democracy and bureaucracy: they offer more positive freedom. In that respect, they are more like romantic relationships or friendships than are democracies and bureaucracies. This tends to make voluntary communities and markets not only more pleasant forms of interaction, but more effective ones—contrary to Weber's confidence in the superior rationality of bureaucratic control.
  •  32
    Populists as Technocrats
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 31 (3-4): 315-376. 2019.
    ABSTRACT An intellectually charitable understanding of populism might begin by recognizing that, since populist citizens tend to be politically uninformed and lacking in higher education, populist ideas are likely to be inarticulate reproductions of the tacit assumptions undergirding non-populist or “mainstream” culture rather than stemming from explicit theoretical constructs, such as an apotheosis of the unity or the will of “the people.” What features of our ambient culture, then, could expla…Read more
  •  31
    The Problem of Epistocratic Identification and the (Possibly) Dysfunctional Division of Epistemic Labor
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 29 (3): 293-327. 2017.
    ABSTRACTHow can political actors identify which putative expert is truly expert, given that any putative expert may be wrong about a given policy question; given that experts may therefore disagree with one another; and given that other members of the polity, being non-expert, can neither reliably adjudicate inter-expert disagreement nor detect when a consensus of experts is misguided? This would not be an important question if the problems dealt with by politics were usually simple ones, in the…Read more