Jeffrey Moriarty

Bentley University
  •  6
    On the Ethics of Selling Psychic Services
    Public Affairs Quarterly 37 (4): 331-351. 2023.
    In many places, it is possible to buy psychic services, including tarot card, palm, and mediumship readings. Yet we have powerful evidence that psychic abilities do not exist. This paper asks whether psychic services should be for sale. I begin by considering whether psychics deceive or mislead buyers. Next, I consider a harm-based argument against the sale of psychic services. Finally, I consider an argument in favor of their sale that appeals to expressive considerations. I conclude with a ten…Read more
  •  47
    Packed with examples, this book offers a clear and engaging overview of ethical issues in business. It begins with a discussion of foundational issues, including the objectivity of ethics, the content of ethical theories, and the debate between capitalism and socialism, making it suitable for the beginning student. It then examines ethical issues in business in three broad areas. The first is the market. Issues explored are what can be sold (the limits of markets) and how it can be sold (ethics …Read more
  •  75
    Why online personalized pricing is unfair
    Ethics and Information Technology 23 (3): 495-503. 2021.
    Online retailers are using advances in data collection and computing technologies to “personalize” prices, i.e., offer goods for sale to shoppers at their reservation prices, or the highest price they are willing to pay. In this paper, I offer a criticism of this practice. I begin by putting online personalized pricing in context. It is not something entirely new, but rather a kind of price discrimination, a familiar pricing practice. I then offer a fairness-based argument against it. When an on…Read more
  •  2
    Deserving Jobs, Deserving Wages
    In Jeffery David Smith (ed.), Normative Theory and Business Ethics, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. pp. 119-146. 2008.
    This chapter applies recent work on desert to two sets of issues in business ethics. The first set of issues concerns who ought to be hired, fired, promoted, and demoted. Call these issues of “job justice.” The second set of issues concerns how much workers, including managers, ought to be paid. Call these issues of “wage justice.” I focus on job and wage justice because considerations of desert play an important, though sometimes tacit, role in discussions of these issues
  • Business Ethics
    Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy. 2019.
    This is annotated bibliography of the field of business ethics. It identifies and summarizes useful journals, textbooks, anthologies, and articles.
  •  8
    Desert-based Justice
    In Serena Olsaretti (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Distributive Justice, Oxford University Press. pp. 152-173. 2018.
    Justice requires giving people what they deserve. Or so many philosophers – and according to many of those philosophers, everyone else – thought for centuries. In the 1970’s and 1980’s, however, perhaps under the influence of Rawls’s (1971) desert-less theory, desert was largely cast out of discussions of distributive justice. Now it is making a comeback. In this chapter I consider recent research on the concept of desert, arguments for its requital, and connections between desert and other dist…Read more
  • Employee Ethics and Rights
    In Eugene Heath, Byron Kaldis & Alexei M. Marcoux (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Business Ethics, Routledge. pp. 474-489. 2018.
    This chapter advances our understanding of the moral contours of the employment relationship. It considers what employers owe their employees, and what employees owe their employers. I begin with a brief discussion of the value and limits of contractual freedom in employment. Then I consider ethical issues in five areas: (1) hiring and firing, (2) compensation, (3) the nature of work, including meaningful work and workplace democracy, (4) privacy, and (5) whistleblowing.
  •  77
    Business Ethics
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2016.
    This article provides an overview of the field of business ethics.
  •  121
    What’s in a Wage? A New Approach to the Justification of Pay
    Business Ethics Quarterly 30 (1): 119-137. 2020.
    ABSTRACT:In this address, I distinguish and explore three conceptions of wages. A wage is a reward, given in recognition of the performance of a valued task. It is also an incentive: a way to entice workers to take and keep jobs, and to motivate them to work hard. Finally, a wage is a price of labor, and like all prices, conveys valuable information about relative scarcity. I show that each conception of wages has its own normative logic, or appropriate justification, and these logics can come a…Read more
  •  77
    On the Origin, Content, and Relevance of the Market Failures Approach
    Journal of Business Ethics 165 (1): 113-124. 2020.
    The view of business ethics that Christopher McMahon calls the “implicit morality of the market” and Joseph Heath calls the “market failures approach” has received a significant amount of recent attention. The idea of this view is that we can derive an ethics for market participants by thinking about the “point” of market activity, and asking what the world would have to be like for this point to be realized. While this view has been much-discussed, it is still not well-understood. This paper se…Read more
  •  37
    Wanted: Positive Arguments for Markets
    Journal of Value Inquiry 51 (4): 641-645. 2017.
    Many people believe that some things, like kidneys or sex, should not be for sale. Let us call these things “contested commodities.” Against this, Brennan and Jaworksi defend “markets without limits” (hereafter: MwL). According to this thesis: “If you may do it for free, you may do it for money” (2016, p. 10). Since we can give away our kidneys for free and have sex for free, we should be able to do these things for money. Brennan and Jaworksi deftly blend rigorous philosophical argument with th…Read more
  •  45
    In early writings, stakeholder theorists supported giving all stakeholders formal, binding control over the corporation, in particular, over its board of directors. In recent writings, however, they claim that stakeholder theory does not require changing the current structure of corporate governance and further claim to be “agnostic” about the value of doing so. This article’s purpose is to highlight this shift and to argue that it is a mistake. It argues that, for instrumental reasons, stakehol…Read more
  •  95
    Teaching & learning guide for business ethics: An overview
    Philosophy Compass 4 (5): 873-876. 2009.
    This article provides some suggestions, including a list of readings, for use in teaching a course in business ethics.
  •  127
    The epistemological argument against desert
    Utilitas 17 (2): 205-221. 2005.
    Most contemporary political philosophers deny that justice requires giving people what they deserve. According to a familiar anti-desert argument, the influence of genes and environment on people's actions and traits undermines all desert-claims. According to a less familiar – but more plausible – argument, the influence of genes and environment on people's actions and traits undermines some desert-claims (or all desert-claims to an extent). But, it says, we do not know which ones (or to what ex…Read more
  •  92
    Smilansky, Arneson, and the asymmetry of desert
    Philosophical Studies 162 (3): 537-545. 2013.
    Desert plays an important role in most contemporary theories of retributive justice, but an unimportant role in most contemporary theories of distributive justice. Saul Smilansky has recently put forward a defense of this asymmetry. In this study, I argue that it fails. Then, drawing on an argument of Richard Arneson’s, I suggest an alternative consequentialist rationale for the asymmetry. But while this shows that desert cannot be expected to play the same role in distributive justice that it c…Read more
  •  198
    Rawls, Self-Respect, and the Opportunity for Meaningful Work
    Social Theory and Practice 35 (3): 441-459. 2009.
    John Rawls says that one of the requirements for stability is “[s]ociety as an employer of last resort” (PLP, lix). He explains: “[t]he lack of . . . the opportunity for meaningful work and occupation is destructive . . . of citizens’ self-respect” (PLP, lix). Rawls implies in these claims that the opportunity for meaningful work is a social basis of self-respect. This constitutes a significant shift in his account of self-respect, one that has been overlooked. I begin by clarifying Rawls’s ac…Read more
  •  38
    The Demands of Stakeholder Theory for Corporate Governance
    Business Ethics Journal Review 4 (8): 47-52. 2016.
    Aimee Barbeau advances a thoughtful critique of my article, “The Connection Between Stakeholder Theory and Stakeholder Democracy: An Excavation and Defense.” Although Barbeau does much to push forward the debate about corporate governance, she does it without undermining my thesis. For what Barbeau has shown is not that stakeholder theorists should not endorse stakeholder boards of directors, but that they should also endorse other ways for stakeholders to participate in decision-making processe…Read more
  •  31
    Risky Pay and the Financial Crisis: Who's Responsible?
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 42 (1): 156-173. 2018.
    According to an existing “environmental” narrative, the financial crisis of 2007-2009 was due in part to executive compensation packages in the financial services industry that incentivized excessive risk-taking. Also according to this narrative, those who have a duty to protect society – principally, government regulators, but also firms themselves – are open to blame for how executives were paid, and must take steps to change executive compensation. This narrative is important but incomplete. …Read more
  •  120
    Participation in the Workplace: Are Employees Special?
    Journal of Business Ethics 92 (3): 373-384. 2010.
    Many arguments have been advanced in favor of employee participation in firm decision-making. Two of the most influential are the "interest protection argument" and the "autonomy argument." I argue that the case for granting participation rights to some other stakeholders, such as suppliers and community members, is at least as strong, according to the reasons given in these arguments, as the case for granting them to certain employees. I then consider how proponents of these arguments might mod…Read more
  •  43
    Ross on desert and punishment
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87 (2). 2006.
    W. D. Ross thinks it is good, other things equal, that people get what they deserve. But he denies that "the principle of punishing the vicious, for the sake of doing so, is that on which the state should proceed in its bestowal of punishments." Ross offers two main arguments for this denial: what I call the "scope argument" and the "state's purpose argument." I argue that both fail. In doing so, I illuminate Ross's distinctive views about desert and the state.
  •  40
    Public Capitalism: The Political Authority of Corporate Executives (review)
    Philosophical Review 124 (3): 422-425. 2015.
    This is a review of Christopher McMahon's book, Public Capitalism.
  •  62
    McMahon on Workplace Democracy
    Journal of Business Ethics 71 (4): 339-345. 2007.
    This paper offers a sympathetic critique of Christopher McMahon’s Authority and Democracy: A General Theory of Government and Management. Although I find fault with some of his arguments, my goal is not to show that these arguments are irreparable, but to highlight issues that deserve further consideration. After defining some terms, first, I raise an objection to McMahon’s rejection of the moral unity of management (MUM) thesis. Second, I draw attention to his “moralization” of the workplace, a…Read more
  •  96
    On the Relevance of Political Philosophy to Business Ethics
    Business Ethics Quarterly 15 (3): 455-473. 2005.
    Abstract:The central problems of political philosophy (e.g., legitimate authority, distributive justice) mirror the central problems of business ethics. The question naturally arises: should political theories be applied to problems in business ethics? If a version of egalitarianism is the correct theory of justice for states, for example, does it follow that it is the correct theory of justice for businesses? If states should be democratically governed by their citizens, should businesses be de…Read more
  •  54
    Liberty, Desert, and the Market (review)
    Business Ethics Quarterly 15 (4): 734-735. 2005.
    This is a review of Serena Olsaretti's book Liberty, Desert, and the Market.
  •  101
    Justice in compensation: a defense
    Business Ethics 21 (1): 64-76. 2011.
    Business ethicists have written much about ethical issues in employment. Except for a handful of articles on the very high pay of chief executive officers and the very low pay of workers in overseas sweatshops, however, little has been written about the ethics of compensation. This is prima facie strange. Workers care about their pay, and they think about it in normative terms. This article's purpose is to consider whether business ethicists' neglect of the normative aspects of compensation is j…Read more
  •  1
    Just Deserts: The Significance of Desert to Distributive Justice
    Dissertation, Rutgers the State University of New Jersey - New Brunswick. 2002.
    The view that justice requires giving people what they deserve is both ancient and plausible. Yet many contemporary political philosophers, including John Rawls and Robert Nozick, have put forward distributive theories that give no place to desert. In this dissertation, I give reason to believe that the contemporary rejection of desert is mistaken, and that desert should be taken seriously by political philosophers. ;This project is incomplete in the sense that I do not say how seriously desert …Read more
  •  50
    Does Distributive Justice Pay? Sternberg’s Compensation Ethics
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (1): 33-48. 2011.
    Compensation has received a great deal of attention from social scientists. Characteristically, they have been concerned with the causes and effects of various compensation schemes. By contrast, few theorists have addressed the normative aspects of compensation. An exception is Elaine Sternberg, who offers in Just Business a comprehensive theory of compensation ethics. This paper critically examines her theory, and argues that the justification she gives for it fails. Its failure is instructive,…Read more
  •  135
    How Much Compensation Can CEOs Permissibly Accept?
    Business Ethics Quarterly 19 (2): 235-250. 2009.
    ABSTRACT:Debates about the ethics of executive compensation are dominated by familiar themes. Many writers consider whether the amount of pay CEOs receive is too large—relative to firm performance, foreign CEO pay, or employee pay. Many others consider whether the process by which CEOs are paid is compromised by weak or self-serving boards of directors. This paper examines the issue from a new perspective. I focus on the dutiesexecutives themselveshave with respect totheir owncompensation. I arg…Read more
  •  257
    Do CEOS get Paid too much?
    Business Ethics Quarterly 15 (2): 257-281. 2005.
    Abstract:In 2003, CEOs of the 365 largest U.S. corporations were paid on average $8 million, 301 times as much as factory workers. This paper asks whether CEOs get paid too much. Appealing to widely recognized moral values, I distinguish three views of justice in wages: the agreement view, the desert view, and the utility view. I argue that, no matter which view is correct, CEOs get paid too much. I conclude by offering two ways CEO pay might be reduced.