• Mississippi State University
    Department of Philosophy & Religion
    Neurobiology and Anatomical Sciences, University of Mississippi Medical Center
    Professor
Starkville, Mississippi, United States of America
  •  13
    Introduction
    Synthese 147 (3): 401-402. 2005.
  •  159
    The previous decade has seen renewed critical interest in the multiple realization argument. These criticisms constitute a "second wave" of challenges to this central argument in late-20th century philosophy of mind. Unlike the first wave, which challenged the premise that multiple realization is inconsistent with reduction or type identity, this second wave challenges the truth of the multiple realization premise itself. Since psychoneural reductionism was prominent among the explicit targets o…Read more
  •  41
    Editors' introduction
    with Gillian Einstein and Valerie Hardcastle
    Brain and Mind 1 (1): 1-6. 2000.
  •  156
    Understanding neural complexity: A role for reduction (review)
    Minds and Machines 11 (4): 467-481. 2001.
      Psychoneural reduction is under attack again, only this time from a former ally: cognitive neuroscience. It has become popular to think of the brain as a complex system whose theoretically important properties emerge from dynamic, non-linear interactions between its component parts. ``Emergence'' is supposed to replace reduction: the latter is thought to be incapable of explaining the brain qua complex system. Rather than engage this issue at the level of theories of reduction versus theories …Read more
  •  82
    Replies
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 4 (3): 285-296. 2005.
    I reply to challenges raised by contributors to this book symposium. Key challenges include (but are not limited to): distancing my new account of reductionism-in-practice from my previous “new wave” account; clarifying my claimed “heuristic” status for higher-level investigations (including cognitive-neuroscientific ones); defending the “reorientation of philosophical desires” I claim to be required by my project; and addressing consideration about normativity
  • Alkire, MT, 370
    with Laurent Auclair, Jodie A. Baird, Kati Balog, Iris R. Bell, Marcia Bernstein, Steven Ravett Brown, Peter Cariani, Wallace Chafe, and Ziya V. Dikman
    Consciousness and Cognition 9 639. 2000.
  • Philosophy of mind and the sciences
    In Stephen P. Stich & Ted A. Warfield (eds.), Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind, Blackwell. 2002.
  •  125
    Multiple realizability
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  12
    Editor's Note
    Brain and Mind 4 (3): 305-305. 2003.
  • Structuralism provides useful resources for advancing our understanding of the intertheoretic reduction relation and its place in the history of science. This paper begins by surveying these resources and assessing their metascientific significance. Nevertheless, important challenges remain. I close by arguing that the reductionism implicit in current scientific practice in a paradigmatic reductionistic scientific field –“molecular and cellular cognition”– is better understood on an “intervene a…Read more
  •  83
    Psychoneural reduction of the genuinely cognitive: Some accomplished facts
    Philosophical Psychology 8 (3): 265-85. 1995.
    The need for representations and computations over their contents in psychological explanations is often cited as both the mark of the genuinely cognitive and a source of skepticism about the reducibility of cognitive theories to neuroscience. A generic version of this anti-reductionist argument is rejected in this paper as unsound, since (i) current thinking about associative learning emphasizes the need for cognitivist resources in theories adequate to explain even the simplest form of this ph…Read more
  •  16
    Phenomenology and cortical microstimulation
    In David Woodruff Smith & Amie Lynn Thomasson (eds.), Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 140. 2005.
  •  155
    Mental anomaly and the new mind-brain reductionism
    Philosophy of Science 59 (2): 217-30. 1992.
    Davidson's principle of the anomalousness of the mental was instrumental in discrediting once-popular versions of mind-brain reductionism. In this essay I argue that a novel account of intertheoretic reduction, which does not require the sort of cross-theoretic bridge laws that Davidson's principle rules out, allows a version of mind-brain reductionism which is immune from Davidson's challenge. In the final section, I address a second worry about reductionism, also based on Davidson's principle,…Read more
  •  18
    Editor's Introduction
    Synthese 141 (2): 153-154. 2004.
  •  50
    Vector subtraction implemented neurally: A neurocomputational model of some sequential cognitive and conscious processes
    with Cindy Worley and Marica Bernstein
    Consciousness and Cognition 9 (1): 117-144. 2000.
    Although great progress in neuroanatomy and physiology has occurred lately, we still cannot go directly to those levels to discover the neural mechanisms of higher cognition and consciousness. But we can use neurocomputational methods based on these details to push this project forward. Here we describe vector subtraction as an operation that computes sequential paths through high-dimensional vector spaces. Vector-space interpretations of network activity patterns are a fruitful resource in rece…Read more
  •  519
    As opposed to the dismissive attitude toward reductionism that is popular in current philosophy of mind, a “ruthless reductionism” is alive and thriving in “molecular and cellular cognition”—a field of research within cellular and molecular neuroscience, the current mainstream of the discipline. Basic experimental practices and emerging results from this field imply that two common assertions by philosophers and cognitive scientists are false: (1) that we do not know much about how the brain wor…Read more
  •  73
    Multiple realizability and psychophysical reduction
    Behavior and Philosophy 20 (1): 47-58. 1992.
    The argument from multiple realizability is that, because quite diverse physical systems are capable of giving rise to identical psychological phenomena, mental states cannot be reduced to physical states. This influential argument depends upon a theory of reduction that has been defunct in the philosophy of science for at least fifteen years. Better theories are now available
  •  37
  •  118
    We introduce a new model of reduction inspired by Kemeny and Oppenheim’s model [Kemeny & Oppenheim 1956] and argue that this model is operative in a “ruthlessly reductive” part of current neuroscience. Kemeny and Oppenheim’s model was quickly rejected in mid-20th-century philosophy of science and replaced by models developed by Ernest Nagel and Kenneth Schaffner [Nagel 1961], [Schaffner 1967]. We think that Kemeny and Oppenheim’s model was correctly rejected, given what a “theory of reduction” w…Read more
  •  50
    Editor's introduction
    Synthese 141 (2): 1-6. 2004.
  •  192
    The Oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2009.
    The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Neuroscience is a state-of-the-art collection of interdisciplinary research spanning philosophy (of science, mind, and ethics) and current neuroscience. Containing chapters written by some of the most prominent philosophers working in this area, and in some cases co-authored with neuroscientists, this volume reflects both the breadth and depth of current work in this exciting field. Topics include the nature of explanation in neuroscience; whether and how cu…Read more