-
72Concept and Time in HegelDialogue 12 (3): 403-422. 1973.To formulate a philosophy of time is not easy, even though it would seem to be the basic requirement for any philosophy which attempts to comprehend the world of nature or of history. The problem is briefly posed: Can the conceptual framework of philosophical thought do justice to the dynamic character of time?The purpose of this paper is not to provide a definitive answer to this question. Its aim is more limited. By discussing carefully the way in which Hegel's philosophy related conceptual th…Read more
-
62Contraries and ContradictoriesThe Owl of Minerva 16 (1): 55-68. 1984.In the year 1841, the sixty-six year old philosopher, Schelling, was installed in the chair of philosophy at Berlin. Because he wanted someone with sufficient authority to combat the influence of Hegel, the new king of Prussia supported his appointment. As Crown Prince he had been concerned about the liberal and subversive elements in Hegel’s political philosophy. In power, he chose an associate of Hegel’s youth to lead the attack, a man who had disappeared from the intellectual scene just as He…Read more
-
56The Syllogisms of Revealed Religion, or the Reasonableness of ChristianityThe Owl of Minerva 18 (1): 29-42. 1986.For the Fnlightenment a continuing question was the reasonableness of Christianity. John Locke devoted a treatise to the question; and it lies at the core of Hume’s essay on miracles, of Lessing’s ugly broad ditch, and of Kant’s religion within the limits of reason alone.
-
54The First Chapter of Hegel’s Larger LogicThe Owl of Minerva 21 (2): 177-183. 1990.Discussions of Hegel’s Logic often concentrate on the first chapter, which starts from pure being and ends with Dasein. Quite regularly commentators find the argument flawed; having thus disposed of its foundation, they dismiss the rest of the logic as equally unreliable.
-
50The “Infinite Agony” of SpiritThe Owl of Minerva 34 (2): 171-186. 2003.Hegel suggests that spirit, in contrast to animal nature, can encounter infinite agony in the death of what was its center, and yet, by dwelling with this loss, emerge into a new form of existence. The paradigm for this move is described toward the end of the chapter on Revealed Religion in the Phenomenology of Spirit. An analysis of the key paragraph introduces a discussion of four questions: Why is this experience triggered by the death of a mediator? What characterizes the spiritual metamorph…Read more
-
48Hegel’s Quest for Certainty (review)The Owl of Minerva 17 (1): 55-58. 1985.This is a good book. The quality of Flay’s analysis grows on the reader as he moves from the introductory comments, through the discussions of self-consciousness, reason, and spirit. We have here an interpretation of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit which does justice to the Hegelian project and at the same time renders most, if not all, of the standard criticisms ineffective. But it is not just a new reading of a work which has challenged many commentators of the past and present. In addition th…Read more
-
48G.W.F. Hegel: Gesammelte Werke. Band 11 (review)The Owl of Minerva 10 (4): 5-6. 1979.When he died in 1831, Hegel had just completed a revision of the first Book of the Science of Logic, “The Doctrine of Being”. Since the revised edition has been consistently used in subsequent printing, the first edition disappeared from view, to surface again only in 1966 when Vanderhoeck and Ruprecht of Gottingen published a facsimile reprint. Along with the never-revised “Doctrine of Essence” of 1813, that original text of Book I has now received elegant treatment in volume 11 of the critical…Read more
-
47Hegel in CanadaThe Owl of Minerva 25 (2): 215-219. 1994.Over the years, in various journals, I have seen lengthy articles about Hegelianism in Poland, in Japan, or in Holland. Never, however, have I seen anything about Hegel studies in Canada. In Europe, for example, anglophone Canadians are simply identified with Americans. On the other hand, in the membership list of the Hegel Society of America, Canadians are lumped together with all the others “outside the U.S.A.”—this despite the fact that three times over the past thirteen biennia Canadians hav…Read more
-
47Contingent CategoriesThe Owl of Minerva 40 (1): 115-131. 2008.By comparing the argument in the first edition of Hegel’s Science of Logic with that of the second we find that he not only introduces significant changes but indicates why he found the changes necessary. As over time he rethought his method in the course of his annual lectures he realised that pure thought should not anticipate results but follow from the inherent sense of each term. The details of his logical method suggest how the novelties that emerge in history can require the introduction …Read more
-
47Hegel and his Critics (review)The Owl of Minerva 22 (2): 227-228. 1991.The essays in this volume do more than simply conjoin Hegel with his critics. There is a full-fledged debate: on occasion the critics gain the upper hand; far more often Hegel rises from the dead to defeat, by anticipation, his opponents.
-
41Hegel's Science of Logic: A Critical Rethinking in Thirty Lectures, by Richard Dien Winfield.: Book Reviews (review)Mind 122 (488): 1213-1215. 2013.
-
39Hegel’s Idea of a Phenomenology of Spirit (review)International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4): 248-250. 2003.
-
36Hegel (review)The Owl of Minerva 17 (1): 92-94. 1985.In the conclusion to his long book on Hegel, Michael Inwood cites a passage describing the way Stephen Spender’s tutors approached the study of philosophy: “This might be described as the Obstacle Race way of teaching philosophy. The whole field of human thought is set out with logical obstacles and the students watch the philosophers race around it.” Inwood mentions it because “it represents … one of the ways in which we should not treat Hegel - disqualifying him from the race altogether on acc…Read more
-
34A Reply from Professor BurbidgeThe Owl of Minerva 14 (4): 10-11. 1983.Di Giovanni’s review of my On Hegel’s Logic in the September 1982 number of The Owl of Minerva fulfilled its own prediction. By responding to my thesis concerning the logic, he transformed my monologue into “an instructive debate on what the nature and value of the Hegelian Logic truly are.” After a thorough and carefully analysis of my “meta-logical” introduction and conclusion, he raises a central question concerning my interpretation of the logic: whether in fact I have fallen prey to psychol…Read more
-
33Das Wissen in Hegels “Wissenschaft der Logik” (review)The Owl of Minerva 17 (1): 86-88. 1985.The title of this book is somewhat misleading. Falk does not write much about knowledge. His intention is to discover the logical method implicit in Hegel’s text, while taking account of Hegel’s claim for “presuppositionlessness.” To avoid ontologizing interpretations, he then suggests that the logic is a transcendental theory, outlining the conditions of cognitive subjectivity.
-
30The Self and its Body in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit (review)International Studies in Philosophy 36 (1): 279-280. 2004.
-
30Hegel on Logic and Religion: The Reasonableness of Christianity (edited book)State University of New York Press. 1992.The 13 essays, most previously published, discuss his logical theory, his applications in general, and his applications to Christianity. Paper edition (unseen), $14.95. Annotation copyrighted by Book News, Inc., Portland, OR
-
28Wissenschaft der Logik. Teil 1 - Die Objektive Logik; Band 1 (review)The Owl of Minerva 18 (1): 67-68. 1986.No one who wants seriously to understand Hegel’s larger Logic can afford to ignore this volume of the collected works. It stands out from all other editions of the German text for two significant reasons.
-
28Philosophy and the Absolute: The Modes of Hegel's SpeculationRobert Grant McRae Dordrecht: Nijhoff, 1985. Pp. ix, 188. $31.00 (review)Dialogue 26 (2): 385-386. 1987.
-
20In Memory of Emil Ludwig Fackenheim, 1916–2003The Owl of Minerva 35 (1-2): 49-52. 2003.At a time when Hegel studies were virtually non-existent in North America, Emil Fackenheim began teaching at the University of Toronto, in a department strongly committed to the history of philosophy. He taught medieval philosophy to third-year students in the honours program, and a course on metaphysics and the philosophy of history to students in fourth year honors, a combination of interests that found expression in his Aquinas Lectures of 1961: Metaphysics and Historicity. It was, however, h…Read more
-
19Man, God, and death in Hegel's phenomenologyPhilosophy and Phenomenological Research 42 (2): 183-196. 1981.
-
14An Interpretation of the Logic of Hegel (review)Idealistic Studies 16 (2): 159-161. 1986.The Logic interpreted by Professor Harris is the Encyclopaedia Logic translated by Wallace. He goes through it chapter by chapter and provides explanations of the various concepts and transitions, using references to the larger Logic, illustrations from the philosophy of nature, and anticipations of subsequent sections. His interpretation is essentially Spinozistic: the ultimate point of reference is the whole. And the dialectical development is the result of thought’s comparing its immediate co…Read more
-
13Contingent CategoriesThe Owl of Minerva 40 (1): 115-131. 2008.By comparing the argument in the first edition of Hegel’s Science of Logic with that of the second we find that he not only introduces significant changes but indicates why he found the changes necessary. As over time he rethought his method in the course of his annual lectures he realised that pure thought should not anticipate results but follow from the inherent sense of each term. The details of his logical method suggest how the novelties that emerge in history can require the introduction …Read more
-
12Der Strukturgedanke in Hegels “Wissenschaft der Logik” (review)International Studies in Philosophy 21 (3): 146-147. 1989.
-
9In Memory of Emil Ludwig Fackenheim, 1916–2003The Owl of Minerva 35 (1-2): 49-52. 2003.At a time when Hegel studies were virtually non-existent in North America, Emil Fackenheim began teaching at the University of Toronto, in a department strongly committed to the history of philosophy. He taught medieval philosophy to third-year students in the honours program, and a course on metaphysics and the philosophy of history to students in fourth year honors, a combination of interests that found expression in his Aquinas Lectures of 1961: Metaphysics and Historicity. It was, however, h…Read more