•  17
    Entailment, Enthymemes, and Formalization
    Journal of Philosophy 83 (10): 572. 1986.
  •  2
    Logics
    Wadsworth Publishing Company. 1997.
    This comprehensive introduction to symbolic logic covers informal logic and the syntax, semantics and metatheory of not only the classical propositional and predicate logics, but also for a number of extensions of classical logic and non-standard logics. It is the first textbook of this kind to provide substantive treatment of more recent developments in logic.
  •  48
    The Move from Is to Good in Environmental Ethics
    Environmental Ethics 31 (2): 135-154. 2009.
    Moves from is to good—that is, principles that link fact to value—are fundamental to environmental ethics. The upshot is fourfold: (1) for nonanthropogenic goods, only those moves from is to good are defensible which conceive goodness as goodness for biotic entities; (2) goodness for nonsentient biotic entities is contribution to their autopoietic functioning; (3) biotic entities also function “exopoietically” to benefit related entities, and these exopoietic benefits are on average greater than…Read more
  •  65
    The Move from Good to Ought in Environmental Ethics
    Environmental Ethics 28 (4): 355-374. 2006.
    The move from good to ought, a premise form found in many justifications of environmental ethics, is itself in need of justification. Of the potential moves from good to ought surveyed, some have considerable promise and others less or none. Those without much promise include extrapolations of obligations based on human goods to nonsentient natural entities, appeals to educated judgment, precautionary arguments, humanistic consequentialist arguments, and justifications that assert that our oblig…Read more
  •  31
    The Move from Is to Good in Environmental Ethics
    Environmental Ethics 31 (2): 135-154. 2009.
    Moves from is to good—that is, principles that link fact to value—are fundamental to environmental ethics. The upshot is fourfold: (1) for nonanthropogenic goods, only those moves from is to good are defensible which conceive goodness as goodness for biotic entities; (2) goodness for nonsentient biotic entities is contribution to their autopoietic functioning; (3) biotic entities also function “exopoietically” to benefit related entities, and these exopoietic benefits are on average greater than…Read more
  •  18
    Sustainability by Leslie Paul Thiele
    Environmental Ethics 37 (1): 121-122. 2015.
  •  264
    The Move from Good to Ought in Environmental Ethics
    Environmental Ethics 28 (4): 355-374. 2006.
    The move from good to ought, a premise form found in many justifications of environmental ethics, is itself in need of justification. Of the potential moves from good to ought surveyed, some have considerable promise and others less or none. Those without much promise include extrapolations of obligations based on human goods to nonsentient natural entities, appeals to educated judgment, precautionary arguments, humanistic consequentialist arguments, and justifications that assert that our oblig…Read more
  •  61
    Reference and perspective in intuitionistic logics
    Journal of Logic, Language and Information 16 (1): 91-115. 2006.
    What an intuitionist may refer to with respect to a given epistemic state depends not only on that epistemic state itself but on whether it is viewed concurrently from within, in the hindsight of some later state, or ideally from a standpoint “beyond” all epistemic states (though the latter perspective is no longer strictly intuitionistic). Each of these three perspectives has a different—and, in the last two cases, a novel—logic and semantics. This paper explains these logics and their semantic…Read more
  • Logica, Seconda edizione
    with Achille C. Varzi and Dennis A. Rohatyn
    McGraw-Hill Italia. 2007.
    Extended revised edition of "Logica" (2003)
  •  65
    Replies to Critics of 'How Harmful are the Average American's Greenhouse Gas Emissions?'
    Ethics, Policy and Environment 16 (1): 111-119. 2013.
    I am grateful to all the respondents to ‘How harmful are the average American's greenhouse gas emissions?’. Their comments were individually and collectively very rich. Since there is...
  •  13
    People tend to rank values of all kinds linearly from good to bad, but there is little reason to think that this is reasonable or correct. This book argues, to the contrary, that values are often partially ordered and hence frequently incomparable. Proceeding logically from a small set of axioms, John Nolt examines the great variety of partially ordered value structures, exposing fallacies that arise from overlooking them. He reveals various ways in which incomparability is obscured: using linea…Read more
  •  1
    REVIEWS-Logics
    with Richard L. Epstein
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (2): 290-290. 2006.
  •  14
    Logica
    with Dennis A. Rohatyn and Achille C. Varzi
    McGraw-Hill Italia. 2003.
    Italian translation of "Schaum's Outline of Theory and Problems of Logic" (1988)
  •  63
    Hope, self-transcendence and environmental ethics
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 53 (2). 2010.
    Environmental ethicists often hold that organisms, species, ecosystems, and the like have goods of their own. But, even given that such goods exist, whether we ought to value them is controversial. Hence an environmental philosophy needs, in addition to an account of what sorts of values there are, an explanation what, how and why we morally ought to value—that is, an account of moral valuing. This paper presents one such an account. Specifically, I aim to show that unless there are eternal good…Read more
  •  51
    Elements of Formal Semantics (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 11 (3): 252-254. 1988.
  •  29
    Healing Appalachia (review)
    Environmental Ethics 32 (2): 219-220. 2010.
  •  8
    Introduction to Special Issue 16 (1)
    Between the Species 16 (1): 3. 2013.
  •  104
    Free logic
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2021.
  •  21
    Healing Appalachia (review)
    Environmental Ethics 32 (2): 219-220. 2010.
  •  46
    Formal Logic (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 12 (4): 424-426. 1989.
  •  399
    How Harmful Are the Average American's Greenhouse Gas Emissions?
    Ethics, Policy and Environment 14 (1): 3-10. 2011.
    It has sometimes been claimed (usually without evidence) that the harm caused by an individual's participation in a greenhouse-gas-intensive economy is negligible. Using data from several contemporary sources, this paper attempts to estimate the harm done by an average American. This estimate is crude, and further refinements are surely needed. But the upshot is that the average American is responsible, through his/her greenhouse gas emissions, for the suffering and/or deaths of one or two futur…Read more
  •  19
    Formal Logic (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 12 (4): 424-426. 1989.
  •  11
    A Land Imperiled not only illustrates the many ways in which the health of this bioregion is being affected, but also provides examples of how the damage can be ...
  •  21
    Comparing Suffering Across Species
    Between the Species 16 (1): 8. 2013.
    Moral life often presents us with trade-offs between the sufferings of some individuals and the sufferings of others. Researchers may need to consider, for example, whether the suffering imposed on animals by a certain line of medical experimentation justifies the relief that the resulting discoveries may bring to others. Often in such cases, the suffering of some individuals is incomparable with—that is neither greater than nor less than nor equal to—the suffering of others. While this complica…Read more
  •  30
    Are There Infinite Welfare Differences among Living Things?
    Environmental Values 26 (1): 73-89. 2017.
    Suppose, as biocentrists do, that even microorganisms have a good of their own - that is, some objective form of welfare. Still, human welfare is vastly greater and more valuable. If it were infinitely greater, individualistic biocentrism would be pointless. But consideration of the facts of evolutionary history and of the conceptual relations between infinity and incommensurability reveals that there are no infinite welfare differences among living things. It follows, in particular, that there …Read more
  •  35
    Domination across Space and Time: Smallpox, Relativity, and Climate Ethics
    Ethics, Policy and Environment 22 (2): 172-183. 2019.
    In the age of exploration western Eurasia came to dominate much of the world, in part unintentionally, via the medium of smallpox. This was domination across great spatial distances. Analogously, w...
  •  26
    Anger, Despondence, and Nonviolence
    The Acorn 17 (1): 53-60. 2017.
    Reflections on anger, despondence, and nonviolence are prompted by student responses to the 2016 election, especially given the likely implications for climate change policy. The author reflects on the value of nonviolence, environmental activism, and participation in a national climate march.