•  25
    Some surprising instabilities in idealized dynamical systems
    Synthese 197 (7): 3007-3026. 2020.
    This paper shows that, in Newtonian mechanics, unstable three-dimensional rigid bodies must exist. Laraudogoitia recently provided examples of one- and two-dimensional homogeneous unstable rigid bodies, conjecturing the instability would persist for three-dimensional bodies in four-dimensional space. My result proves that, if one admits non homogeneous balls or hollow spheres, then the conjecture is true without having to resort to tetra-dimensionality. Furthermore, I show that instability also …Read more
  •  19
    Priest on the paradox of the gods
    Analysis 60 (2): 152-155. 2000.
  •  21
    A variant of Benardete's paradox
    Analysis 63 (2): 124-131. 2003.
  •  26
    The Convergence Approach to Benardete’s Paradox
    Philosophia 51 (3): 1353-1367. 2023.
    The paper analyses Benardete's paradox of the gods from a more general perspective (the convergence approach) than several of the most important proposals made to date, but in close relation (and sharp contrast) with them. The new theory, based on the notion of limit, is systematically applicable in different possible scenarios involving a denumerable infinity of objects. In particular, it reveals in what way ω-consistency can be compromised in an otherwise consistent description of such "infini…Read more
  •  21
    Unmoved movers: a very simple and novel form of indeterminism
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (3): 1-23. 2022.
    It is common knowledge that the Aristotelian idea of an unmoved mover was abandoned definitively with the advent of modern science and, in particular, Newton’s precise formulation of mechanics. Here I show that the essential attribute of an unmoved mover is not incompatible with such mechanics; quite the contrary, it makes this possible. The unmoved mover model proposed does not involve supertasks, and leads both to an outrageous form of indeterminism and a new, accountable form of interaction. …Read more
  •  15
    Fluids, Molecules and Paradoxes of Infinity
    Philosophia 50 (4): 1945-1953. 2022.
    Several paradoxes of infinity have recently featured in this journal involving gases distributed in a denumerable infinite series of compartments. I shall demonstrate in this paper that:a) None of these new paradoxes applies where the gases comply with both Boyle’s law and Avogadro’s law. As several of these new paradoxes expressly require compliance with Boyle’s law, it is unclear, in principle, as to whether there is a plausible model of gas that is able to uphold them all.b) Notwithstanding a…Read more
  •  23
    There is broad consensus as to what a rigid body is in classical mechanics. The idea is that a rigid body is an undeformable body. In this paper I show that, if this identification is accepted, there are therefore rigid bodies which are unstable. Instability here means that the evolution of certain rigid bodies, even when isolated from all external influence, may be such that their identity is not preserved over time. The result is followed by analyzing supertasks that are possible in infinite s…Read more
  •  17
    Discussion. Earman and Norton on supertasks that generate indeterminism
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (1): 137-141. 1999.
    In a recent discussion, Earman and Norton [(1998)] propose a classification of supertasks that generate indeterminism which is flawed. An emendation is presented here.
  •  7
    An Infinite System with Gravitation
    Synthese 135 (3): 339-346. 2003.
    The paper shows a new example of nonuniqueness of the solutionto Newtonian equations of motion for infinite gravitational systems. Unlike otherexamples, the gravitational field presents no singularity, nor are the non-gravitational forcesintroduced in the model singular (in particular, there are no collisions). The result is also ofinterest because it points to an interesting limitation of the elementary (Newtonian) formulationof classical mechanics.
  •  15
    A Note on some New Infinity Puzzles
    Philosophia 48 (4): 1483-1491. 2020.
    In this short note I argue that, using the type of configurations put forward in a recent paper by Laraudogoitia in this same journal, new paradoxes of infinity of a completely different nature can be formulated.
  •  23
    A Note on some New Infinity Puzzles
    Philosophia 48 (4): 1483-1491. 2020.
    In this short note I argue that, using the type of configurations put forward in a recent paper by Laraudogoitia in this same journal, new paradoxes of infinity of a completely different nature can be formulated.
  •  36
    Some New Infinity Puzzles
    Philosophia 48 (3): 1093-1099. 2020.
    Salmon was the first to speak explicitly of paradoxes of kinematics. In this short note I introduce a new class of infinity puzzles. Following natural terminology, they should actually be called static paradoxes.
  •  26
    The Magic Potion Paradox
    Philosophia 45 (3): 1227-1234. 2017.
    This paper introduces a new infinite paradox. The main novelty is that it poses problems of causality in a very different form from to the one in use until now. By means of a probabilistic generalization, the paradox shows that the disposition to act according to a specific plan is not always necessary to derive causal effects in Benardete-type contexts involving infinity. It also suggests that, in such cases, the explanation for those causal effects requires a propensity interpretation of proba…Read more
  •  67
    CORNEA against theism
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 48 (2): 81-87. 2000.
  •  61
    What the Tortoise Said to Achilles
    Philosophia 42 (2): 405-411. 2014.
    Continuing the conversation between Achilles and the tortoise begun by Carroll, this paper proves that, in a supertask context, there are free actions (in general, contingent states of affairs) that can be predicted by means of purely logical reasons
  •  50
    Why dynamical self-excitation is possible
    Synthese 119 (3): 313-323. 1999.
    In Pérez Laraudogoitia (1996), I introduced a simple example of a supertask that involved the possibility of spontaneous self-excitation and, therefore, of a particularly interesting form of indeterminism in classical dynamics. Alper and Bridger (1998) criticised (among other things) this result. In the present article, I answer their criticisms. In what follows I assume familiarity both with Pérez Laraudogoitia (1996) and Alper and Bridger’s subsequent article.
  •  76
    The inverse spaceship paradox
    Synthese 178 (3): 429-435. 2011.
    In this article I propose what I call the inverse spaceship paradox. The article's interest lies in the fact that, contrary to what appears to be an implicit agreement in the literature on indeterminism, it shows that coming from infinity can be a perfectly predictable and therefore deterministic process in a classical universe
  •  22
    Rigidity, instability and dimensionality
    Synthese 195 (9): 4047-4062. 2018.
    The paper takes a detailed look at a surprising new aspect of the dynamics of rigid bodies. Far from the usual consideration of rigid body theory as a merely technical chapter of classical physics, I demonstrate here that there are solutions to the conservation equations of mechanics that imply the spontaneous, unpredictable splitting of a rigid body in free rotation, something that has direct implications for the problem of causality. The paper also shows that the instability revealed in indete…Read more
  •  143
    Some relativistic and higher order supertasks
    Philosophy of Science 65 (3): 502-517. 1998.
    The first aim of this paper is to introduce a new way of looking at supertasks in the light of special relativity which makes use of the elementary dynamics of relativistic point particles subjected to elastic binary collisions and constrained to move unidimensionally. In addition, this will enable us to draw new physical consequences from the possibility of supertasks whose ordinal type is higher than the usual ω or ω * considered so far in the literature. Thus, the paper shows how an entire co…Read more
  •  22
    The New String Paradox
    Philosophy of Science 80 (1): 143-154. 2013.
    I shall begin by discussing Benardete’s string paradox. Then, a new puzzle involving supertasks and causality is proposed and discussed. Finally, the new string paradox facilitates the discovery of a surprising example of irreversible mechanical process.
  • Una paradoja lógica del inventor
    Pensamiento 51 (200): 283-284. 1995.
  •  72
    On the dynamics of Alper and Bridger
    Synthese 131 (2). 2002.
    Bridger and Alper (1999) maintain that the nonphysical featuresof the supertasks described by Pérez Laraudogoitia (1996) involving a system containing an infinite number of particles may be avoided by introducing, in a specific way, Hilbert space in classical dynamics. I argue that it is possible to interpret their proposal in two ways, neither of which is acceptable for the purpose for which it was introduced.
  •  114
    The supertask argument against countable additivity
    Philosophical Studies 168 (3): 619-628. 2014.
    This paper proves that certain supertasks constitute counterexamples to countable additivity even in the frame of an objective (not subjective, à la de Finetti) conception of probability. The argument requires taking conditional probability as a primitive notion
  •  63
    Zeno and flow of information
    Synthese 190 (3): 439-447. 2013.
    Although the current literature on supertasks concentrates largely on their supposed physical implications (extending the tradition of Zeno’s classical paradoxes of movement), in this study I propose a new model of supertask that explores for the first time some of their information-related consequences and I defend these consequences from a possible criticism.
  •  45
    Taking Self‐Excitations Seriously: On Angel's Initial Condition
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (2): 319-326. 2003.
    In a recent article, L. Angel ([2001]) argues that if we do not implement Newtonian physics adding to it a certain usual type of boundary condition, then this leads to the rejection of what he calls the P principle: ‘the composition of contact interactions does not create a noncontact interaction.’ Here I shall demonstrate that this conclusion does not follow. However, as will be made clear, this in no way diminishes the interest or importance of the model introduced by Angel in his paper. 1 Int…Read more
  •  83
    Supertasks
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  210
    Infinity machines and creation ex nihilo
    Synthese 115 (2): 259-265. 1998.
    In this paper a simple model in particle dynamics of a well-known supertask is constructed (the supertask was introduced by Max Black some years ago). As a consequence, a new and simple result about creation ex nihilo of particles can be proved compatible with classical dynamics. This result cannot be avoided by imposing boundary conditions at spatial infinity, and therefore is really new in the literature. It follows that there is no reason why even a world of rigid spheres should be eternal, a…Read more
  •  16
    On The Dynamics Of Alper And Bridger
    Synthese 131 (2): 157-171. 2002.
    Bridger and Alper (1999) maintain that the nonphysical featuresof the supertasks described by Pérez Laraudogoitia (1996) involving a system containing an infinite number of particles may be avoided by introducing, in a specific way, Hilbert space in classical dynamics. I argue that it is possible to interpret their proposal in two ways, neither of which is acceptable for the purpose for which it was introduced.
  • Paradojas lógico-físicas. El concepto de sistema físico
    Pensamiento 43 (170): 197-205. 1987.