•  19
    Ewing, AC
    with Mark Timmons
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
  • Moral Fictionalism: How and Why?
    In Richard Joyce & Stuart Brock (eds.), Moral Fictionalism and Religious Fictionalism, Oxford University Press. pp. 64-85. 2024.
  •  16
    In his recent book The Value Gap (2021), Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen defends a pluralist view of final goodness and goodness-for, according to which neither concept is analysable in terms of the other. In this paper I defend a specific version of monism, namely so-called ‘Mooreanism’, according to which goodness-for is analysable partly in terms of final goodness. Rønnow-Rasmussen offers three purported counterexamples to Mooreanism. I argue that Mooreanism can accommodate two of them. The third is mo…Read more
  •  7
    Value superiority
    In Iwao Hirose & Jonas Olson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory, . pp. 225-248. 2015.
  •  4
    The value of existence
    In Iwao Hirose & Jonas Olson (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory, . pp. 424-444. 2015.
  • Oxford Handbook of Value (edited book)
    with Hirose J.
    Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
  •  60
    The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory (edited book)
    Oxford University Press USA. 2015.
    Value theory, or axiology, looks at what things are good or bad, how good or bad they are, and, most fundamentally, what it is for a thing to be good or bad. Questions about value and about what is valuable are important to moral philosophers, since most moral theories hold that we ought to promote the good. This Handbook focuses on value theory as it pertains to ethics, broadly construed, and provides a comprehensive overview of contemporary debates pertaining not only to philosophy but also to…Read more
  •  3
    Regimenting Reasons
    Theoria 71 (3): 203-214. 2005.
    The Belief‐Desire model (the B‐D model) of reasons for action has been subject to much criticism lately. Two of the most elaborate and trenchant expositions of such criticisms are found in recent works by Jonathan Dancy (2000) and Fred Stoutland (2002). In this paper we set out to respond to the central pieces of their criticisms. For this purpose it is essential to sort out and regiment different senses in which the term ‘reason’ may be used. It is necessary to go beyond common philosophical pr…Read more
  •  72
    Quasi-realism and normative certitude
    Synthese 198 (8): 7861-7869. 2020.
    Just as we can be more or less certain that there is extraterrestrial life or that Goldbach’s conjecture is correct, we can be more or less certain about normative matters, such as whether euthanasia is permissible or whether utilitarianism is true. However, accommodating the phenomenon of degrees of normative certitude is a difficult challenge for non-cognitivist and expressivist views, according to which normative judgements are desire-like attitudes rather than beliefs. Several attempts have …Read more
  •  67
  •  20
    Hume's sentimentalism: Not non-cognitivism
    Belgrade Philosophical Annual 1 (34): 95-111. 2021.
    This paper considers and argues against old and recent readings of Hume according to which his account of moral judgement is non-cognitivist. In previous discussions of this topic, crucial metaethical distinctions-between sentimentalism and non-cognitivism and between psychological and semantic non-cognitivism-are often blurred. The paper aims to remedy this and argues that making the appropriate metaethical distinctions undermines alleged support for non-cognitivist interpretations of Hume. The…Read more
  •  69
    Kriegel on Brentano on value and fittingness
    European Journal of Philosophy 31 (2): 479-485. 2021.
    European Journal of Philosophy, EarlyView.
  •  44
    Nihilism and the Epistemic Profile of Moral Judgment
    In Aaron Zimmerman, Karen Jones & Mark Timmons (eds.), Routledge Handbook on Moral Epistemology, Routledge. 2018.
    Moral nihilism is the view that there are no moral facts or moral truths. It is the ontological component of moral error theory, which is the best-known and most comprehensive metaethical theory that involves moral nihilism. My main aim is to discuss some consequences of endorsing moral error theory or believing to some degree that moral error theory is true. In §2, I consider the implications for ordinary moral thought and discourse and the epistemological consequences for moral theorizing. In …Read more
  •  60
  •  23
    Are there moral facts? According to moral nihilism, the answer is no. Some moral nihilists are moral error theorists, who think that moral judgements purport to refer to moral facts, but since there are no moral facts, moral judgements are uniformly false or untrue. Terence Cuneo has recently raised an original and potentially very serious objection to moral error theory. According to Cuneo’s ‘normative theory of speech’, normative facts, some of which are moral facts, are crucially involved in …Read more
  •  2
    Getting Real about Moral Fictionalism
    In Russ Shafer-Landau (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, Volume 6, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  28
    The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory (edited book)
    with Iwao Hirose
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    Value theory, or axiology, looks at what things are good or bad, how good or bad they are, and, most fundamentally, what it is for a thing to be good or bad. Questions about value and about what is valuable are important to moral philosophers, since most moral theories hold that we ought to promote the good. This Handbook focuses on value theory as it pertains to ethics, broadly construed, and provides a comprehensive overview of contemporary debates pertaining not only to philosophy but also to…Read more
  •  165
    What Matters in Metaethics
    Analysis 79 (2): 341-349. 2019.
    In the first two volumes of On What Matters,1 Derek Parfit pursued a conciliatory project in normative ethics, which sought to dissolve the disagreement between the most plausible versions of Kantianism, contractualism and rule consequentialism. Parfit was less conciliatory in his meta-ethics, however. Does Parfit’s conciliatory project in metaethics succeed? We shall begin to address this question in the next section by, first, trying to get a grip on Parfit’s position, which now goes by the n…Read more
  •  50
    Moral Practice after Error Theory: Negotiationism
    In Richard Garner & Richard Joyce (eds.), The End of Morality: Taking Moral Abolitionism Seriously, Routledge. pp. 113-130. 2018.
    We first deal with a few preliminary matters and discuss what-if any-distinct impact belief in moral error theory should have on our moral practice. Second, we describe what is involved in giving an answer to our leading question and take notice of some factors that are relevant to what an adequate answer might look like. We also argue that the specific details of adequate answers to our leading question will depend largely on context. Third, we consider three extant answers to our leading quest…Read more
  •  141
    Moral and Epistemic Error Theory : The Parity Premise Reconsidered
    In Conor McHugh, Jonathan Way & Daniel Whiting (eds.), Metaepistemology, Oxford University Press. pp. 107-121. 2018.
    Many moral error theorists hold that moral facts are irreducibly normative. They also hold that irreducible normativity is metaphysically queer and conclude that there are no irreducibly normative reasons and consequently no moral facts. A popular response to moral error theory utilizes the so-called ‘companions in guilt’ strategy and argues that if moral reasons are irreducibly normative, then epistemic reasons are too. This is the Parity Premise, on the basis of which critics of moral error th…Read more
  •  85
    Debunking arguments in metaethics are often presented as particularly challenging for non‐naturalistic versions of moral realism. The first aim of this paper is to explore and defend a response on behalf of non‐naturalism. The second aim of the paper is to argue that although non‐naturalism’s response is satisfactory, this does not mean that debunking arguments are metaethically uninteresting. They have a limited and indirect role to play in the exchange between non‐naturalists and moral error t…Read more
  •  45
    Hume on Is and Ought, by Pigden Charles R. : Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010, pp. xiv + 352, £74.00 (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 91 (4): 821-824. 2013.
    No abstract
  •  116
    The Metaphysics of Reasons
    In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, Oxford University Press. pp. 255-274. 2018.
    This chapter focuses exclusively on normative reasons. Normative reasons count in favor of actions and attitudes like beliefs, desires, feelings, and emotions. Section 11.2 explores the common ground concerning the metaphysics of reasons. We shall see that the really controversial metaphysical issues in metanormative theorizing about reasons arise with respect to the metaphysics of the reason relation. The two subsequent sections therefore go beyond the common ground and consider competing accou…Read more
  •  56
    Essays in Moral Skepticism (review)
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism. forthcoming.
    _ Source: _Page Count 6
  •  67
    Two Kinds of Ethical Intuitionism: Brentano’s and Reid’s
    The Monist 100 (1): 106-119. 2017.
    This paper explores Franz Brentano’s metaethics by comparing it to Thomas Reid’s. Brentano and Reid share a commitment to moral realism and they are both aptly classified as intuitionists concerning moral knowledge and the nature of moral judgment. However, their respective versions of intuitionism are importantly different, in ways that reflect more general differences between their respective epistemological views. Sections III and IV of the paper focus more exclusively on Brentano’s metaethic…Read more