Brown University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 2003
New Brunswick, NJ, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Epistemology
Areas of Interest
Epistemology
Metaphysics
  • There is no immediate Justification
    In Matthias Steup & John Turri (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Blackwell. 2013.
  •  73
    Knowledge from Blindspots
    In Rodrigo Borges & Ian Schnee (eds.), Illuminating Errors: New Essays on Knowledge from Non-Knowledge, Routledge. pp. 76-91. 2023.
    No False Lemmas (NFL) says: necessarily, S’s belief that p is knowledge only if it is not inferred from any falsehood. Its proponents argue that alleged counterexamples to NFL are really cases of knowledge despite falsehood, wherein the false premise is inessential to the inference; perhaps some nearby truth does the justificatory heavy-lifting. We argue that there can be cases of inferential knowledge from a blindspot premise. Given that in such cases the relevant falsehood is essential to the …Read more
  •  73
    Schroeder on reasons, experience, and evidence
    Philosophical Studies 181 (2): 607-616. 2024.
  •  35
    Reply to my critics
    Philosophical Studies 180 (8): 2507-2519. 2023.
  •  27
    Precis of being rational and being right
    Philosophical Studies 180 (8): 2503-2506. 2023.
  •  14
    On Sturgeon’s “The rational Mind” (review)
    Philosophical Studies 180 (10): 3205-3213. 2023.
  •  63
    Philosophical Issues, Volume 30, Issue 1, Page 54-70, October 2020.
  •  143
    Being Rational and being Right
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    In Being Rational and Being Right, Juan Comesaña argues for a cluster of theses related to the rationality of action and belief. His starting point is that rational action requires rational belief but tolerates false belief. From there, Comesaña provides a novel account of empirical evidence according to which said evidence consists of the content of undefeated experiences. This view, which Comesaña calls "Experientialism," differs from the two main views of empirical evidence on offer nowada…Read more
  •  195
    We Are (Almost) All Externalists Now
    Philosophical Perspectives 19 (1): 59-76. 2005.
    In this paper I argue against Mentalism, the claim that all the factors that contribute to the epistemic justification of a doxastic attitude towards a proposition by a subject S are mental states of S. My objection to mentalism is that there is a special kind of fact (what I call a "support fact") that contributes to the justification of any belief, and that is not mental. My argument against mentalism, then, is the following: Anti-mentalism argument: 1. If mentalism is true, then support facts…Read more
  •  201
    Justified vs. Warranted Perceptual Belief: Resisting Disjunctivism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (2): 367-383. 2007.
    In this paper I argue that McDowell's brand of disjunctivism about perceptual knowledge is ill‐motivated. First, I present a reconstruction of one main motivation for disjunctivism, in the form of an argument that theories that posit a “highest common factor” between veridical and non‐veridical experiences must be wrong. Then I show that the argument owes its plausibility to a failure to distinguish between justification and warrant (where “warrant” is understood as whatever has to be added to t…Read more
  •  694
    Rationality and Truth
    In Julien Dutant & Fabian Dorsch (eds.), The New Evil Demon, Oxford University Press. forthcoming.
    The traditional view in epistemology is that we must distinguish between being rational and being right (that is also, by the way, the traditional view about practical rationality). In his paper in this volume, Williamson proposes an alternative view according to which only beliefs that amount to knowledge are rational (and, thus, no false belief is rational). It is healthy to challenge tradition, in philosophy as much as elsewhere. But, in this instance, we think that tradition has it right. In…Read more
  •  616
    Evidentialism and Reliabilism are two of the main contemporary theories of epistemic justification. Some authors have thought that the theories are not incompatible with each other, and that a hybrid theory which incorporates elements of both should be taken into account. More recently, other authors have argued that the resulting theory is well- placed to deal with fine-grained doxastic attitudes (credences). In this paper I review the reasons for adopting this kind of hybrid theory, paying att…Read more
  •  437
    A Plea for Falsehoods
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 100 (2): 247-276. 2020.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
  •  407
    Empirical justification and defeasibility
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 7): 1771-1786. 2018.
    Two truisms about empirical justification are that experience plays a crucial role in it and that it is defeasible. There are, of course, different ways of developing these truisms into philosophical theories. I favor one particular view about the role of experience in empirical justification which may be thought to lead to problems in accommodating its defeasibility. My aim in this paper is to argue that the problems are illusory, based on an entrenched misconception how defeaters work.
  •  577
    Having False Reasons
    In Clayton Littlejohn & John Turri (eds.), Epistemic Norms, Oxford University Press. pp. 59-80. 2014.
  • The Ways of Reason
    Dissertation, Brown University. 2003.
    This dissertation is about rationality, both practical rationality , and theoretical rationality . I argue that there are interesting similarities as well as interesting differences between practical and theoretical rationality. One of the similarities is that both of them are essentially related to the explanation of actions and beliefs, and one of the differences is that whereas theoretical rationality has the hyper-external aim of truth, practical rationality has the non-hyper-external aim of…Read more
  •  247
    Is Evidence Knowledge?
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 80 (2): 447-454. 2010.
    We argue that if evidence were knowledge, then there wouldn’t be any Gettier cases, and justification would fail to be closed in egregious ways. But there are Gettier cases, and justification does not fail to be close in egregious ways. Therefore, evidence isn’t knowledge.
  •  150
    What lottery problem for reliabilism?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (1): 1-20. 2009.
    It can often be heard in the hallways, and occasionally read in print, that reliabilism runs into special trouble regarding lottery cases. My main aim in this paper is to argue that this is not so. Nevertheless, lottery cases do force us to pay close attention to the relation between justification and probability.
  •  184
    Knowledge and Subjunctive Conditionals
    Philosophy Compass 2 (6): 781-791. 2007.
    What relation must hold between a fact p and the corresponding belief that p for the belief to amount to knowledge? Many authors have recently proposed that the relation can be captured by subjunctive conditionals. In this paper I critically evaluate the main proposals along those lines
  • En defensa de un externalismo epistémico
    Revista Latinoamericana de Filosofia 28 (2): 173-200. 2002.
  •  228
    The diagonal and the demon
    Philosophical Studies 110 (3). 2002.
    Reliabilism about epistemic justification - the thesis that what makes a belief epistemically justified is that it was produced by a reliable process of belief-formation - must face two problems. First, what has been called "the new evil demon problem", which arises from the idea that the beliefs of victims of an evil demon are as justified as our own beliefs, although they are not - the objector claims - reliably produced. And second, the problem of diagnosing why skepticism is so appealing des…Read more
  •  524
    Perceptual reasons
    Philosophical Studies 173 (4): 991-1006. 2016.
    The two main theories of perceptual reasons in contemporary epistemology can be called Phenomenalism and Factualism. According to Phenomenalism, perceptual reasons are facts about experiences conceived of as phenomenal states, i.e., states individuated by phenomenal character, by what it’s like to be in them. According to Factualism, perceptual reasons are instead facts about the external objects perceived. The main problem with Factualism is that it struggles with bad cases: cases where perceiv…Read more
  •  5
    Escepticismo semántico y teorías del significado
    Análisis Filosófico 18 (2): 143-149. 1998.
    In several works H. Putnam has developed an argument addressed against "realist" semantic theories (in particular, against causal theories of reference ). In this paper I argue that Putnam's argument is weaker than what is generally supposed, as Devitt has shown in Realism and Truth. I disagree, however, with Devitfs latest strategy against model-theoretic arguments as presented in an ''Afterword'' to that book.
  •  145
    Could there be exactly two things?
    Synthese 162 (1). 2008.
    Many philosophers think that, necessarily, any material objects have a fusion (let’s call that doctrine “Universalism”). In this paper I point out a couple of strange consequences of Universalism and related doctrines, and suggest that they are strange enough to constitute a powerful argument against those views
  •  726
    Is Evidence of Evidence Evidence?
    with Eyal Tal
    Noûs 51 (1): 95-112. 2017.
    We examine whether the "evidence of evidence is evidence" principle is true. We distinguish several different versions of the principle and evaluate recent attacks on some of those versions. We argue that, whatever the merits of those attacks, they leave the more important rendition of the principle untouched. That version is, however, also subject to new kinds of counterexamples. We end by suggesting how to formulate a better version of the principle that takes into account those new counterexa…Read more
  • Security and Dreams in the Epistemology of Sosa
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 28 (1): 75-81. 2009.