• Speech acts
    with R. Harnish
    In , . 1979.
  •  1
    Loaded Words
    Oxford University Press. 2018.
  • The emperor's new 'knows'
    In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  •  2
    Language, Logic, and Form
    In Dale Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell. 2006.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Sentential Connectives Quantifiers and Quantified Noun Phrases Proper Names and Individual Constants Adjectives Adverbs and Events Utterance Modifiers Logical Form as Grammatical Form Summary.
  •  18
    Speech Acts and Pragmatics
    In Michael Devitt & Richard Hanley (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language, Wiley-blackwell. 2006.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Performative Utterances Locutionary, Illocutionary, and Perlocutionary Acts Classifying Illocutionary Acts Communicative Speech Acts and Intentions Conversational Implicature and Impliciture Conventional Implicature The Semantic‐Pragmatic Distinction Applications of the Semantic‐Pragmatic Distinction.
  •  64
    Literal Meaning (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2): 487-492. 2007.
  •  23
    Change in View: Principles of Reasoning
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 (4): 761-764. 1988.
  •  16
    The Structure of Emotions
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (2): 362-366. 1988.
  •  69
    Picoeconomics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4): 981-983. 1995.
    There is a simple view of motivation on which desires are like pain-killers; they come in different strengths, and their strength determines their efficacy. That is, the stronger a desire the greater its motivational force and, when two desires conflict, the stronger one “wins out” over the weaker. This view makes it puzzling how anyone could ever exhibit “strength of will” and act on the weaker desire, even when it is a desire for something more highly valued than what is more strongly desired.…Read more
  • Context Dependence
    In Manuel García-Carpintero & Max Kölbel (eds.), The Continuum companion to the philosophy of language, Continuum International. 2012.
  •  5
    Failed Reference and Feigned Reference: Much ado about Nothing
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 26 (1): 359-374. 1985.
    Nothing can be said about a nonexistent object, but something can be said about the act of (unsuccessfully) attempting to refer to one or, as in fiction, of pretending to refer to one. Unsuccessful reference, whether by expressions or by speakers, can be explained straightforwardly within the context of the theory of speech acts and communication. As for fiction, there is nothing special semantically, as to either meaning or reference, about its language. And fictional discourse is just a distin…Read more
  • The Semantics and Pragmatics of Reference
    In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  3
  •  23
    Acknowledgment
    with Pauline Jacobson, Shalom Lappin, Martin Stokhof, Daniel Buring, Peter Lasersohn, Thomas Ede, Paul Dekker Beth Levin Zimmermann, Julie Sedivy, and Ben Russell
    Linguistics and Philosophy 28 781-782. 2005.
    Acknowledgment of peer reviewers
  •  18
    Acknowledgment
    with Pauline Jacobson, Daniel Buring, Paul Dekker, Shalom Lappin, Peter Lasersohn, Beth Levin, Julie Sedivy, Martin Stokhof, Thomas Ede, and Ian Lyons
    Linguistics and Philosophy 27 777-778. 2004.
    Acknowledgment of peer reviewers
  •  15
    Meaning and the Moral Sciences
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40 (1): 137-139. 1979.
  • Drawing More Lines: Response to Depraetere and Salkie
    In Raphael Salkie & Ilse Depraetere (eds.), Semantics and Pragmatics: Drawing a Line, Springer Verlag. 2016.
  •  964
    Linguistic Communication and Speech Acts
    with Robert M. Harnish
    MIT Press. 1979.
    a comprehensive, somewhat Gricean theory of speech acts, including an account of communicative intentions and inferences, a taxonomy of speech acts, and coverage of many topics in pragmatics
  •  1
    A Rationale for Reliabilism
    In Sven Bernecker & Fred I. Dretske (eds.), Knowledge: Readings in Contemporary Epistemology, Oxford University Press. 2000.
  •  7
    Perspectives on Self-deception (review)
    Noûs 26 (4): 495-504. 1992.
  •  94
    Anyone weary of endless philosophical debate on belief reports will find welcome relief in this book. Talking not just about belief talk but about belief itself, it offers much that is new, interesting, and subtle. The central thesis, though interestingly and subtly developed, is not exactly new. It is a version of the “hidden indexical theory” (HIT) of..
  • Two Problems of Perception
    Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley. 1968.
  •  166
    I am often asked to explain the difference between my notion of impliciture (Bach 1994) and the relevance theorists’ notion of explicature (Sperber and Wilson 1986; Carston 2002). Despite the differences between the theoretical frameworks within which they operate, the two notions seem very similar. Relevance theorists describe explicatures as “developments of logical forms,” whereas I think of implicitures as “expansions” or “completions” of semantic contents (depending on whether or not the se…Read more
  •  41
    Relevant questions
    with Robert M. Harnish
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4): 711. 1987.
  •  205
    Context Dependence
    In Manuel García-Carpintero & Max Kölbel (eds.), The Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Continuum International. 2012.
    All sorts of things are context-dependent in one way or another. What it is appropriate to wear, to give, or to reveal depends on the context. Whether or not it is all right to lie, harm, or even kill depends on the context. If you google the phrase ‘depends on the context’, you’ll get several hundred million results. This chapter aims to narrow that down. In this context the topic is context dependence in language and its use. It is commonly observed that the same sentence can be used to convey…Read more
  •  123
    1. Sentences have implicatures. (11, 14, 19)** 2. Implicatures are inferences. (12. 14) 3. Implicatures can’t be entailments. 4. Gricean maxims apply only to implicatures. (16, 17) 5. For what is implicated to be figured out, what is said must be determined first. (12, 13) 6. All pragmatic implications are implicatures. 7. Implicatures are not part of the truth-conditional contents of utterances. (20) 8. If something is meant but unsaid, it must be implicated. (20) 9. Scalar “implicatures” are i…Read more