•  64
    This paper presents a new explanation of how preferring the simplest theory compatible with experience assists one in finding the true answer to a scientific question when the answers are theories or models. Inquiry is portrayed as an unending game between science and nature in which the scientist aims to converge to the true theory on the basis of accumulating information. Simplicity is a topological invariant reflecting sequences of theory choices that nature can force an arbitrary, convergent sc…Read more
  •  30
    Scientific methods may be viewed as procedures for converging to the true answer to a given empirical question. Typically, such methods converge to the truth only if certain empirical presuppositions are satisfied, which raises the question whether the presuppositions are satisfied. Another scientific method can be applied to this empirical question, and so forth, occasioning an empirical regress. So there is an obvious question about the point of such a regress. This paper explains how to asses…Read more
  •  52
    We argue that uncomputability and classical scepticism are both reflections of inductive underdetermination, so that Church's thesis and Hume's problem ought to receive equal emphasis in a balanced approach to the philosophy of induction. As an illustration of such an approach, we investigate how uncomputable the predictions of a hypothesis can be if the hypothesis is to be reliably investigated by a computable scientific method
  •  39
    Kevin T. Kelly. General Characteristics of Inductive Inference Over Arbitrary Sets of Data Representations
  •  39
    Philosophical logicians proposing theories of rational belief revision have had little to say about whether their proposals assist or impede the agent's ability to reliably arrive at the truth as his beliefs change through time. On the other hand, reliability is the central concern of formal learning theory. In this paper we investigate the belief revision theory of Alchourron, Gardenfors and Makinson from a learning theoretic point of view
  •  89
    Thoroughly Modern Meno
    In Clark Glymour & Kevin T. Kelly (eds.), Inference, Explanation, and Other Frustrations: Essays in the Philosophy of Science, University of California Press: Berkeley. pp. 3--22. 1992.
    Clark Glymour and Kevin T. Kelly. Thoroughly Modern Meno
  •  83
    Formal Learning Theory and the Philosophy of Science
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988. 1988.
    Formal learning theory is an approach to the study of inductive inference that has been developed by computer scientists. In this paper, I discuss the relevance of formal learning theory to such standard topics in the philosophy of science as underdetermination, realism, scientific progress, methodology, bounded rationality, the problem of induction, the logic of discovery, the theory of knowledge, the philosophy of artificial intelligence, and the philosophy of psychology.
  •  14
    Getting to the Truth through Conceptual Revolutions
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990. 1990.
    There is a popular view that the alleged meaning shifts resulting from scientific revolutions are somehow incompatible with the formulation of general norms for scientific inquiry. We construct methods that can be shown to be maximally reliable at getting to the truth when the truth changes in response to the state of the scientist or his society.
  •  18
    Worst case complexity analyses of algorithms are sometimes held to be less informative about the real difficulty of computation than are expected complexity analyses. We show that the two most common representations of problem solving in cognitive science each admit aigorithms that have constant expected complexity, and for one of these representations we obtain constant expected complexity bounds under a variety of probability measures.
  •  223
    The Automated Discovery of Universal Theories
    Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh. 1986.
    This thesis examines the prospects for mechanical procedures that can identify true, complete, universal, first-order logical theories on the basis of a complete enumeration of true atomic sentences. A sense of identification is defined that is more general than those which are usually studied in the learning theoretic and inductive inference literature. Some identification algorithms based on confirmation relations familiar in the philosophy of science are presented. Each of these algorithms is…Read more
  •  102
    Here is the usual way philosophers think about science and induction. Scientists do many things— aspire, probe, theorize, conclude, retract, and refine— but successful research culminates in a published research report that presents an argument for some empirical conclusion. In mathematics and logic there are sound deductive arguments that fully justify their conclusions, but such proofs are unavailable in the empirical domain because empirical hypotheses outrun the evidence adduced for them. Ind…Read more
  •  72
    Learning theory and epistemology
    In Ilkka Niiniluoto, Matti Sintonen & Jan Woleński (eds.), Handbook of Epistemology, Kluwer Academic. pp. 183--203. 2004.
  •  33
    Philosophical logicians proposing theories of rational belief revision have had little to say about whether their proposals assist or impede the agent's ability to reliably arrive at the truth as his beliefs change through time. On the other hand, reliability is the central concern of formal learning theory. In this paper we investigate the belief revision theory of Alchourron, Gardenfors and Makinson from a learning theoretic point of view.
  •  55
    Efficient convergence implies ockham's razor
    Proceedings of the 2002 International Workshop on Computational Models of Scientific Reasoning and Applications. 2002.
    A finite data set is consistent with infinitely many alternative theories. Scientific realists recommend that we prefer the simplest one. Anti-realists ask how a fixed simplicity bias could track the truth when the truth might be complex. It is no solution to impose a prior probability distribution biased toward simplicity, for such a distribution merely embodies the bias at issue without explaining its efficacy. In this note, I argue, on the basis of computational learning theory, that a fixed simplic…Read more
  •  100
    in Handbook of the Philosophy of Information, J. van Behthem and P. Adriaans, eds., to appear
  •  117
    Clark Glymour, Richard Scheines, Peter Spirtes and Kevin Kelly. Discovering Causal Structure: Artifical Intelligence, Philosophy of Science and Statistical Modeling
  •  5
    Getting to the Truth Through Conceptual Revolutions
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990 (1): 89-96. 1990.
    [I]t would be absurd for us to hope that we can know more of any object than belongs to the possible experience of it or lay claim to the least knowledge of how anything not assumed to be an object of possible experience is determined according to the constitution that it has in itself.* * *It would be… a still greater absurdity if we conceded no things in themselves or declared our experience to be the only possible mode of knowing things….[Kant, Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics]A certain …Read more
  •  26
    Book Review: Living Together and Christian Ethics (review)
    Studies in Christian Ethics 16 (2): 119-123. 2003.
  •  56
    Theory discovery from data with mixed quantifiers
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 19 (1). 1990.
    Convergent realists desire scientific methods that converge reliably to informative, true theories over a wide range of theoretical possibilities. Much attention has been paid to the problem of induction from quantifier-free data. In this paper, we employ the techniques of formal learning theory and model theory to explore the reliable inference of theories from data containing alternating quantifiers. We obtain a hierarchy of inductive problems depending on the quantifier prefix complexity of t…Read more
  •  100
    Inductive inference from theory Laden data
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 21 (4). 1992.
    Kevin T. Kelly and Clark Glymour. Inductive Inference from Theory-Laden Data
  •  164
    Belief revision theory concerns methods for reformulating an agent's epistemic state when the agent's beliefs are refuted by new information. The usual guiding principle in the design of such methods is to preserve as much of the agent's epistemic state as possible when the state is revised. Learning theoretic research focuses, instead, on a learning method's reliability or ability to converge to true, informative beliefs over a wide range of possible environments. This paper bridges the two per…Read more
  •  67
    A Further Tribute to Paul McGuire
    The Chesterton Review 5 (2): 323-323. 1979.
  •  143
    Learning theory and the philosophy of science
    Philosophy of Science 64 (2): 245-267. 1997.
    This paper places formal learning theory in a broader philosophical context and provides a glimpse of what the philosophy of induction looks like from a learning-theoretic point of view. Formal learning theory is compared with other standard approaches to the philosophy of induction. Thereafter, we present some results and examples indicating its unique character and philosophical interest, with special attention to its unified perspective on inductive uncertainty and uncomputability
  •  127
    The logic of success
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (4): 639-666. 2000.
    The problem of induction reminds us that science cannot wait for empirical hypotheses to be verified and Duhem’s problem reminds us that we cannot expect full refutations either. We must settle for something less. The shape of this something less depends on which features of full verification and refutation we choose to emphasize. If we conceive of verification and refutation as arguments in which evidence entails the hypothesis or its negation, then the central problem of the philosophy of scie…Read more
  •  3
    Book Review: Living Together and Christian Ethics (review)
    Studies in Christian Ethics 16 (2): 119-123. 2003.