•  6
    Rziha, John. The Christian Moral Life: Directions for the Journey to Happiness (review)
    Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 31 (1-2): 195-196. 2019.
  •  7
    Michael Bergmann and Jeffrey Brower, eds. Reason & Faith: Themes from Richard Swinburne (review)
    Journal of Analytic Theology 6 748-753. 2018.
  •  7
    How can a loving God also be a God of wrath? God's wrath stands out in the minds of many as the single most puzzling aspect of God's character. Often Christians who would like to reconcile divine love with divine wrath―while remaining faithful to the Bible―can't figure out how to do so. Kevin Kinghorn and Stephen Travis offer a way forward. Using a philosophically informed line of argument and a careful study of the relevant biblical texts, Kinghorn and Travis show how these two aspects of God's…Read more
  •  2
    A Framework for the Good
    University of Notre Dame Press. 2016.
    This book provides an ethical framework for understanding the good and how we can experience it in increasing measure. In Part 1, Kevin Kinghorn offers a formal analysis of the meaning of the term "good," the nature of goodness, and why we are motivated to pursue it. Setting this analysis within a larger ethical framework, Kinghorn proposes a way of understanding where noninstrumental value lies, the source of normativity, and the relationship between the good and the right. Kinghorn defends a w…Read more
  •  14
    Our everyday conversations reveal the widespread assumption that positive and negative treatment of others can be justified on the grounds that “they deserve it.” But what is it exactly to 'deserve' something? This book offers an exploration into how we came to have this concept, along with an explanation why people feel so strongly that redress is needed when outcomes are undeserved. The book probes for that core concern which is common to the range of everyday desert claims people make. Wh…Read more
  •  984
    While we may not be able simply to choose what we believe, there is still scope for culpability for what we come to belief. I explore here the distinction between culpable and non-culpable theistic unbelief, investigating the process of self-deception to which we can voluntarily contribute in cases where we do become culpable for failing to believe something.
  •  19
    A Case of Insincerity: What Does it Mean to Deceive Someone?
    In Philip Tallon & David Baggett (eds.), The Philosophy of Sherlock Holmes, University Press of Kentucky. pp. 37-48. 2012.
    In unpacking the nature of deception, we'll want to ask what conditions would need to be met in order rightly to conclude that an act of deception has taken place. The literary stories about Sherlock Holmes provide a large pool of examples of misdirection, whereby Holmes is able to stay one step ahead of his adversaries. These examples are used to show the inadequacy of a number of purported definitions of deception. I then settle on one definition that does seem adequate. One odd outcome of…Read more
  •  269
    In his essay, "Fine-Tuning and Multiple Universes", Roger White examines the extent to which a multiple-universe hypothesis lessens the ’surprisingness’ that our universe should be life-sustaining. White offers two main conclusions. His first conclusion -- that the existence of our world is not itself evidence for the existence of multiple universes -- is sound. However, his second conclusion is that, on the hypothesis that multiple universes exist, the further hypothesis of an intelligent desig…Read more
  •  58
    Christian theologians have historically described a 'saving faith in God' as containing a fundamental element of 'belief'. However, philosophers present strong arguments exist that we are not capable of freely deciding which beliefs we will hold. Rather, we simply find ourselves believing things as the evidence before us seems to dictate. So, if belief is indeed involuntary, and if certain beliefs are requisite for Christian faith, then how can the matter of one's salvation rest on whether one h…Read more
  •  222
    Authoritarian Tennis Parents: Are Their Children Any Worse Off?
    In David Baggett (ed.), Tennis and Philosophy, University Press of Kentucky. pp. 90-106. 2010.
    It is common to think of controlling tennis parents–the ones who push their children to succeed from a young age–as compromising their children’s well-being. But is this really the case? A look at the question of what makes any person’s life go well for her, as well as what does and doesn’t compromise well-being.
  •  21
    Plot Twists and Surprises: Why are Some Things Improbable?
    In David Baggett & William Drumin (eds.), Hitchcock and Philosophy, Open Court. pp. 215-227. 2007.
    The movies of Alfred Hitchcock provide continuous plot twists and surprising revelations. But what exactly makes an event improbable? Examples from Hitchcock movies are used to demonstrate how we might talk about different kinds of probability. A larger discussion of evidential probability then follows in which the movie Rear Window is used to illustrate methods of induction. More specifically, the reasoning process of Jimmy Stewart's character involves him asking the very questions that Bay…Read more
  •  16
    In a scene from C. S. Lewis's The Magician's Nephew, a handful of humans watch as Aslan sings the new world of Narnia into existence. Everyone is amazed to find they can understand the animals speaking--except Uncle Andrew, who only hears barkings, howlings, and the like. But why is this so? Lewis gives hints throughout the book that Uncle Andrew does not possess the kinds of characteristics that later philosophers would identify as epistemic virtues. In this article I introduce Lorraine Cod…Read more
  •  17
    Heaven (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 21 (1): 120-124. 2004.
  •  90
    Questions of Identity: Is the Hulk the Same Person as Bruce Banner?
    In Tom Morris & Matt Morris (eds.), Superheroes and Philosophy, Open Court. pp. 223-236. 2005.
    In settling the question whether The Hulk is the same person as Bruce Banner, we need to ask what grounds our personal identity in the first place. What makes it the case that you are the 'same person' today that you were 10 years ago? Physical, mental, and causal accounts of identity are shown to be lacking. In the end, continuity of personal identify must be found in the relationships one has with others--and how others view us. In this instance ontology actually does seem to depend on epist…Read more
  •  10
    The varying motivations of early morning runners becomes a useful way of distinguishing a 'decision' from an 'intentional action'. Runners may differ greatly on the number of actual decisions that are made in the course of a run--even while they perform roughly the same number of intentional actions. In showing how this is so, it also becomes clear why a single action can have multiple descriptions.
  •  7
    Heaven (review)
    Faith and Philosophy 21 (1): 120-124. 2004.