•  901
    The value of responsibility gaps in algorithmic decision-making
    Ethics and Information Technology 25 (1): 1-11. 2023.
    Many seem to think that AI-induced responsibility gaps are morally bad and therefore ought to be avoided. We argue, by contrast, that there is at least a pro tanto reason to welcome responsibility gaps. The central reason is that it can be bad for people to be responsible for wrongdoing. This, we argue, gives us one reason to prefer automated decision-making over human decision-making, especially in contexts where the risks of wrongdoing are high. While we are not the first to suggest that respo…Read more
  •  434
    What Relational Egalitarians Should (Not) Believe
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 27 (2). 2024.
    Relational egalitarianism is a theory of justice according to which justice requires that people relate as equals. According to some relational egalitarians, X and Y relate as equals if, and only if, they (1) regard each other as equals; and (2) treat each other as equals. In this paper, we argue that relational egalitarians must give up 1.
  •  352
    In this paper, we defend what we call the ‘Hybrid View’ of privacy. According to this view, an individual has privacy if, and only if, no one else forms an epistemically warranted belief about the individual’s personal matters, nor perceives them. We contrast the Hybrid View with what seems to be the most common view of what it means to access someone’s personal matters, namely the Belief-Based View. We offer a range of examples that demonstrate why the Hybrid View is more plausible than the Bel…Read more
  •  316
    Why algorithmic speed can be more important than algorithmic accuracy
    with Jakob Mainz, Jens Christian Bjerring, and Sissel Godtfredsen
    Clinical Ethics 18 (2): 161-164. 2023.
    Artificial Intelligence (AI) often outperforms human doctors in terms of decisional speed. For some diseases, the expected benefit of a fast but less accurate decision exceeds the benefit of a slow but more accurate one. In such cases, we argue, it is often justified to rely on a medical AI to maximise decision speed – even if the AI is less accurate than human doctors.
  •  305
    Proper Address and Epistemic Conditions for Acting on Sexual Consent
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 52 (1): 69-100. 2023.
    Philosophy &Public Affairs, Volume 52, Issue 1, Page 69-100, Winter 2024.
  •  266
    The stakes associated with an algorithmic decision are often said to play a role in determining whether the decision engenders a right to an explanation. More specifically, “high stakes” decisions are often said to engender such a right to explanation whereas “low stakes” or “non-high” stakes decisions do not. While the overall gist of these ideas is clear enough, the details are lacking. In this paper, we aim to provide these details through a detailed investigation of what we will call the “Si…Read more
  •  232
    Two Reasons for Subjecting Medical AI Systems to Lower Standards than Humans
    Acm Proceedings of Fairness, Accountability, and Transaparency (Facct) 2023 1 (1): 44-49. 2023.
    This paper concerns the double standard debate in the ethics of AI literature. This debate essentially revolves around the question of whether we should subject AI systems to different normative standards than humans. So far, the debate has centered around the desideratum of transparency. That is, the debate has focused on whether AI systems must be more transparent than humans in their decision-making processes in order for it to be morally permissible to use such systems. Some have argued that…Read more
  •  230
    Doxastic Affirmative Action
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1-18. forthcoming.
    According to the relational egalitarian theory of justice, justice requires that people relate as equals. To relate as equals, many relational egalitarians argue, people must (i) regard each other as equals, and (ii) treat each other as equals. In this paper, we argue that, under conditions of background injustice, such relational egalitarians should endorse affirmative action in the ways in which (dis)esteem is attributed to people as part of the regard-requirement for relating as equals.
  •  194
    The Privacy Dependency Thesis and Self-Defense
    AI and Society 1-11. forthcoming.
    If I decide to disclose information about myself, this act can undermine other people’s ability to effectively conceal information about themselves. One case in point involves genetic information: if I share ‘my’ genetic information with others, I thereby also reveal genetic information about my biological relatives. Such dependencies are well-known in the privacy literature and are often referred to as ‘privacy dependencies’. Some take the existence of privacy dependencies to generate a moral d…Read more
  •  192
    What We Owe Past Selves
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 40 (5): 936-950. 2023.
    Some say that we should respect the privacy of dead people. In this article, I take this idea for granted and use it to motivate the stronger claim that we sometimes ought to respect the privacy of our past selves.
  •  158
    Privacy rights and ‘naked’ statistical evidence
    Philosophical Studies 178 (11): 3777-3795. 2021.
    Do privacy rights restrict what is permissible to infer about others based on statistical evidence? This paper replies affirmatively by defending the following symmetry: there is not necessarily a morally relevant difference between directly appropriating people’s private information—say, by using an X-ray device on their private safes—and using predictive technologies to infer the same content, at least in cases where the evidence has a roughly similar probative value. This conclusion is of the…Read more
  •  146
    The Moral Significance of Privacy Dependencies
    with Jakob Thrane Mainz
    Philosophy and Technology 36 (4): 1-19. 2023.
    Often, when we share information about ourselves, we contribute to people learning personal things about others. This may happen because what we share about ourselves can be used to infer personal information about others. Such dependencies have become known as privacy dependencies in the literature. It is sometimes claimed that the scope of the right to privacy should be expanded in light of such dependencies. For example, some have argued that inferring information about others can violate the…Read more
  •  109
    Consensual Discrimination
    Philosophical Quarterly. forthcoming.
    What makes discrimination morally bad? In this paper, we discuss the putative badness of a case of consensual discrimination to show that prominent accounts of the badness of discrimination—appealing, inter alia, to harm, disrespect and inequality—fail to provide a satisfactory answer to this question. In view of this, we present a more promising account.
  •  72
    The Right to Privacy, Control Over Self‐Presentation, and Subsequent Harm
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 37 (1): 141-154. 2020.
    Andrei Marmor has recently offered a narrow interpretation of the right to privacy as a right to having a reasonable amount of control over one's self‐presentation. He claims that the interest people have in preventing others from abusing their personal information to do harm is not directly protected by the right to privacy. This article rejects that claim and defends a view according to which concerns about abuse play a central role in fleshing out the appropriate scope of a general right to p…Read more
  •  60
    Digital Self-Defence: Why you Ought to Preserve Your Privacy for the Sake of Wrongdoers
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 25 (2): 233-248. 2022.
    Most studies on the ethics of privacy focus on what others ought to do to accommodate our interest in privacy. I focus on a related but distinct question that has attracted less attention in the literature: When, if ever, does morality require us to safeguard our own privacy? While we often have prudential reasons for safeguarding our privacy, we are also, at least sometimes, morally required to do so. I argue that we, sometimes, ought to safeguard our privacy for the sake of the possible wrongd…Read more
  •  53
    How Privacy Rights Engender Direct Doxastic Duties
    Journal of Value Inquiry 56 (4): 547-562. 2022.
  •  30
    Mainz and Uhrenfeldt have recently claimed that a violation of the right to privacy can be defined successfully under reliance on the notion of ‘Negative Control’. In this reply, I show that ‘Negative Control’ is unrelated to privacy right violations. It follows that control theorists have yet to put forth a successful normative account of privacy.
  •  22
    What We Owe Past Selves
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 40 (5): 936-950. 2023.
    Some say that we should respect the privacy of dead people. In this article, I take this idea for granted and use it to motivate the stronger claim that we sometimes ought to respect the privacy of our past selves.
  •  20
    In this paper, we defend what we call the ‘Hybrid View’ of privacy. According to this view, an individual has privacy if, and only if, no one else forms an epistemically warranted belief about the individual’s personal matters, nor perceives them. We contrast the Hybrid View with what seems to be the most common view of what it means to access someone’s personal matters, namely the Belief-Based View. We offer a range of examples that demonstrate why the Hybrid View is more plausible than the Bel…Read more
  •  13
    Correction to: Privacy rights and ‘naked’ statistical evidence
    Philosophical Studies 178 (11): 3797-3797. 2021.
    A correction to this paper has been published: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01640-1.