•  146
    Is Leibniz’s Theory of Personal Identity Coherent?
    The Leibniz Review 9 117-129. 1999.
    "In this paper, I shall consider the several ways in which interpreters, since 1976, have attempted to challenge the premises of Wilson's argument, and so have tried to rescue Leibniz's theory from Wilson's charge of incoherence. I shall argue that only one of these ways stands any chance of being successful." (S. 117/118)\nDiskussion zu Margaret Wilson: Leibniz : self-consciousness and immortality in the Paris notes and after. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 58 (1976), S. 335 - 352 (vgl. …Read more
  •  97
    Leibniz on causation
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  97
    Stepping Back Inside Leibniz’s Mill
    with Paul Lodge
    The Monist 81 (4): 553-572. 1998.
    Leibniz’s reasons for rejecting materialism are complex and often rely on assumptions that are deeply puzzling to contemporary philosophers. However, the discussion of these issues in § 17 of the Monadology has received a lot of attention over the past couple of decades. For it is here that Leibniz presents the most well known version of his “mill argument.”
  •  92
    Leibniz on Concurrence and Efficient Causation
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (3): 317-338. 2008.
    Leibniz defends concurrentism, the view that both God and created substances are causally responsible for changes in the states of created substances. Interpretive problems, however, arise in determining just what causal role each plays. Some recent work has been revisionist, greatly downplaying the causal role played by created substances—arguing instead that according to Leibniz only God has productive causal power. Though bearing some causal responsibility for changes in their perceptual stat…Read more
  •  39
  •  30
    Consolation and Cartesian Immortality
    Faith and Philosophy 20 (2): 189-207. 2003.
    Like many other Christian philosophers, past and present, Descartes envisions an "afterlife" for the soul after bodily death. Some, both Christian and non-Christian, including Geach, Strawson and Williams, have argued that the afterlife Descartes envisions is far from the attractive state heaven is supposed to be. Others, including Leibniz, Russier, and Cottingham, have argued that a Cartesian afterlife represents a state of existence that cannot even be rationally desired. But I shall argue …Read more
  •  30
    Leibniz on Embodiment and the Moral Order
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (3): 377-396. 1999.
  •  24
    In this paper I present a novel view of the ontological status of possible objects for Descartes. Specifically, I claim that possible objects just are innate ideas considered objectively. In the act of creation, God creates possibilities—in all its richness—in the form of innate ideas. Thus, in acts of thinking, one may clearly and distinctly perceive, via one’s innate ideas, that such and such is possible. To argue this, I first analyze and critique two competing views—one from Calvin Normore w…Read more
  •  17
    Unpacking the Monad
    with Kenneth Clatterbaugh
    The Monist 79 (3): 408-425. 1996.
  •  17
    In this paper I present a novel view of the ontological status of possible objects for Descartes. Specifically, I claim that possible objects just are innate ideas considered objectively. In the act of creation, God creates possibilities—in all its richness—in the form of innate ideas. Thus, in acts of thinking, one may clearly and distinctly perceive, via one’s innate ideas, that such and such is possible. To argue this, I first analyze and critique two competing views—one from Calvin Normore w…Read more
  •  14
    Leibniz on Concurrence and Efficient Causation
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 46 (3): 317-338. 2008.
    Leibniz defends concurrentism, the view that both God and created substances are causally responsible for changes in the states of created substances. Interpretive problems, however, arise in determining just what causal role each plays. Some recent work has been revisionist, greatly downplaying the causal role played by created substances—arguing instead that according to Leibniz only God has productive causal power. Though bearing some causal responsibility for changes in their perceptual stat…Read more
  •  4
    Leibniz on Embodiment and the Moral Order
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 37 (3): 377-396. 1999.
  •  4
    "We are omniscient but confused," says Leibniz. He also says that we live in the best of all possible worlds, yet do not causally interact. So what are we? Leibniz is known for many things, including the ideality of space and time, calculus, plans for a universal language, theodicy, and ecumenism. But he is not known for his ideas on the self and personal identity. This book shows that Leibniz offers an original, internally coherent theory of personal identity, a theory that stands on its own ev…Read more
  • Folktales and Philosophy for Children
    Analytic Teaching and Philosophical Praxis 25 (2): 80-88. 2006.
  • G. W. Leibniz: Personhood, Moral Agency, and Meaningful Immortality
    Dissertation, University of Washington. 1998.
    This dissertation covers a sadly neglected area of Leibniz's thought--his account of personhood and its concomitant doctrines of moral agency and meaningful immortality. It defends an interpretation of Leibniz's philosophy that is unique in the following respects. Some scholars have worried that Leibniz wavers as to whether sameness of substance is necessary for personal identity. Leibnizian persons, they wonder aloud, might therefore be more appropriately thought of as Lockean unities of consci…Read more
  • Thinking machines and moral agency in Leibniz's nouveaux essais
    Studia Leibnitiana 30 (2): 178-193. 1998.
    Leibniz dit souvent que toutes les substances individuelles et seulement les substances individuelles peuvent être agents moraux authentiques. Mais, dans un passage fascinant des "Nouveaux essais", Leibniz semble concéder à John Locke que si les machines pensantes existaient, elles pourraient être des agents moraux authentiques. Ce serait une concession très significative considérant le fait que pour Leibniz les machines ne sont pas du tout des substances authentiques, mais de simple agrégats de…Read more